Darek ERIKSSON :
Contibution à la Théorie de la Modélisation Systémique
Cette étude des fondements théoriques et
épistémologiquse de la Modélisation
Systémique, rédigée par un chercheur
suédois pariculiérement actif au sein duProgramme européen MCX, Darek Eriksson,
a été publiée en 1997, dans la Revue "Cybernetics and Human
Knowing". Vol. 4 no. 2-3 1997.
Le programme européen MCX remercie chaleureusement le rédacteur en chef
et infatiguable animateur de la revue , Sören Brier http://www.flec.kvl.dk/sbr/index.htm
et son éditeur (publisher) Ed. of Cybernetics & Human Knowing www.imprint.co.uk/C&HK, de
nous autoriser confraternellement à publier ici la version
intégrale de cet article original.
A
Principal Exposition of Jean-Louis Le Moigne’s
Systemic
Theory
Darek M. Eriksson
Department of Informatics and Systems Science,
School of Business
Administration and Social Sciences, Luleå
University of Technology, Sweden.
Darek.Eriksson@ies.luth.se
Abstract
The
aim of this article is to present to the reader the theoretical construction of
Jean-Louis Le Moigne. It starts with a discussion of the background that is
relevant for this construction, which is: a few words about Le Moigne himself,
some influences on his thinking and an overview of the theoretical framework
together with some domains of application. The following exposition of Le
Moigne’s Systemics (LMS) is articulated in three groups: the what, the why and
the how of knowing.
The what presents the two basic hypotheses
of LMS’ epistemological version, called Projective Constructivist Epistemology.
These are: the phenomenological and the teleological hypotheses. The three
dominating properties of the first hypothesis, that is the irreversibility, the
recursivity and the dialectics of knowing, are presented as well.
The why question presents the criterion for
validation, which is projective (or cognitive) feasibility, to be contrasted
with the positivist’s aspiration for objective truth. This presents LMS’
solution to the dilemma between objectivity and relativism. Projective
feasibility is possible due to the so-called social contract and the autonomy
of science as a domain of thought, both are discussed.
The
third question, the how, presents a
set of cognitive instruments for knowledge constitution. These may be
articulated in three sub-categories: modelling rationality, systemic modelling
and inforgetic theory.
Under
the label of modelling rationality the following topics are discussed:
formalism, procedural rationality, conjunctive or self-referential system of
logic and the discussion of the method for conduct of good reason.
Secondly,
systemic modelling discusses: complexity, modelling, the canonic model of a General
System, LMS’ modelling instrument called Systemography, the canonic model of a
General Process, the canonic model of Information Processing System, LMS’
instrument for articulation of complex systems called Teleological Complexification
of Functional Levels, a general and a priori identification of pertinent levels
of complexification of a complex system’s organisation as manifested in the
canonic model called Decision-Information-Organisation System, and finally the
paradigm of an active organisation: Eco-Auto-Re-Organisation with its canonic
model of organisation, the latter is a conflictful conjunction of three
recursive functions: to produce and self-produce, to relate and self-relate, to
maintain and self-maintain.
Thirdly,
inforgetic theory refers to the conceptual relation between information and
organisation. It includes: the canonic model of information:
Signified-Sign-Signification, the first principle of inforgetics: the principle
of self-organisation, and the second principle of inforgetics: the principle of
intelligent action. Finally, the article gives a brief summing up of the significance
of Le Moigne’s contribution.
1. Introduction
For
over a quarter of this century, Jean-Louis Le Moigne has developed a particular
version of constructivist epistemology and a theory of systemics founded on
that epistemology. His works are not well known to the Anglo-American
community. This paper is an attempt to remedy this by making a general
presentation of the main ideas of Le Moigne’s works.[1]
The
present exposition starts with a short background presentation that includes a
few words about Le Moigne, a brief discussion about the intellectual influence
on his thinking and a brief overview of his theories. That introduction will
then be followed by the main exposition of Le Moigne’s theoretical construction.
Finally, we briefly sketch a summing up of this contribution’s significance.
2. Some Background
2.1. A few words about J-L Le Moigne
Jean-Louis
Le Moigne, born in 1931, is professor of Systems Science at Aix-Marseille University
III in France. Le Moigne was educated as an engineer. For a short while he
participated in the French military intervention in Algeria, which left some
marks on his thinking. Le Moigne spent 13 years as a scientist, engineer and
then manager in a large French industrial company. He was one of the firsts in
France to apply an operations research approach to problem solving in
industrial domains. That activity seems to have left some traces. Indeed he was
very unhappy with the natural science and engineering approaches behind problem
solving in human activity systems. He considered them to be limiting and
inadequate for such tasks.
Due
to the student revolt in the 1960’s, the French universities started to look
for managers to join them, in order to contribute with their experience and
thinking. Le Moigne was one of these. For a start, he spent a year in the
United States, first at the Harvard School of Economics and then at Massachusetts
Institute of Technology. In his comments (Le Moigne 1989a) it is clear that he
was surprised and disappointed about the superficiality that education implied.
It is also clear, that this period exposed him to some ideas that came to
affect his thinking and theory construction in a certain way. An example of the
latter is H.A. Simon’s (1969) ”The science of the artificial”, or Z.S.
Zannetos’ (1968) ”Toward intelligent management information systems”.
When
Le Moigne started his teaching at the university, he found himself in a
problematic situation. He was supposed to teach a discipline that was called by
the Anglo-American world ‘Management Information Systems’, that is, the
application of computer systems to problem solving in socio-economic contexts.
This intellectual domain, then rather ill-defined, did not have enough
theoretical qualities. Le Moigne considered the small theoretical contributions
that existed either fragmentary or, due to his own experience, unusable. He
started to look for more substantial theories and used the domain of system
science as a guide in his endeavour. For more than 25 years he has constructed,
re-constructed and conjuncted theories in order to support his students with
cognitive instruments in their future professions. Among others, Le Moigne is
the co-founder and director of the research group GRASCE[2]
that has its laboratories at Aix-en-Provence. He is chairman of MCX, which is
an organisation for modelling of complexity. He has published numerous of articles
and books, mainly in French. (Le Moigne 1989a)
2.2. Some influences on Le Moigne’s thinking
Le
Moigne (1994) often states that the main impression for his works is due to
what he calls the golden triangle of PSM. This is J. Piaget, H.A. Simon and E.
Morin. Indeed these influences are not difficult to recognise. He also mentions
sometimes the so-called three V’s, that is L. da Vinci, G.B. Vico and P. Valéry
(Le Moigne 1994). These are certainly not as dominating as the golden triangle
but have still left some visible traces. The two triples are however not the
only influences. One of the main merits of Le Moigne’s work is the ability to
bring together large amounts of literature from very different disciplines into
a coherent unity, which few would expect possible. A sample of some names may
be mentioned: G. Bachelard, G. Bateson, A. Bogdanov, K. Boulding, H. von
Foerster, A. Korzybski, R. Mattessich, F. Varela, N. Wiener.
The
discussion of all these influences would certainly require another article. A
short comment on the golden triangle will have to suffice. Jean Piaget’s works
on genetic epistemology (Piaget 1970) are a clear foundation for Le Moigne’s
own epistemological dialect. Further, Le Moigne (1977-1994) synthesised
Piaget’s (1968) structuralist theory with N. Wiener’s (1948) cybernetic. That
exercise resulted in Le Moigne’s systemic model, which is the kernel of his
General Systems Theory (Le Moigne 1977-1994). Piaget’s (1967) system of
sciences is clearly visible in Le Moigne’s (1995b) own contribution to that
topic, also affected by Morin’s notion of cyclical complexity. It was Piaget -
shortly before he passed away - who personally encouraged Le Moigne to continue
his ongoing project.
Herbert
A. Simon’s contribution to science in general is broad, concerned with, for
example organisation theory, management science, economics, computer science,
artificial intelligence and psychology. These aspects are visible in Le
Moigne’s approach, for example in his conception of systems science as a
science of design (Simon 1969). Further, Newell and Simon’s (1972) Information
Processing System theory has a central role as an instrument for representation
and symbol manipulation. Simon’s (1976a) conception of social organisation -
that to organise is to decide rather than to produce, as the Taylorian school
postulated - is visible. Further, the science of decision (Newell & Simon
1972, Simon 1982) and the strong teleological emphasis is also evident.
Finally, following Simon (1976b), Le Moigne has focused a procedural reasoning
rather than an substantive.
Lastly,
Edgar Morin’s monumental project in conceiving of a new science, as expressed
in La Méthode (Morin 1977, 1980, 1982, 1986, 1991; Le Moigne & Atias 1984)
has had quite a general influence. Morin’s conception of complexity implies the
necessity for complexification rather than reduction, this in order to make
phenomena intelligible. This approach seems to be fundamental for Le Moigne. Further,
Morin’s dialogic or recursive approach to reasoning is evident in Le Moigne’s
conception of the general model of organisation and also in his cyclic system
of sciences (Le Moigne 1990a, 1995b).
Altogether,
the conjunction of the golden triangle is probably most elegantly manifested in
Le Moigne’s conception of a decision epistemology (Le Moigne 1982, 1986a,
1995a). While Piaget was inspired by Husserl, Simon by Carnap and Morin by the
Hegelian dialectic, Le Moigne’s conjunction of the three perspectives has led
to the emergence of a new argument. Hence the epistemological spectacles of the
three contributors are exchanged for the newly emerged one.
Finally,
while Le Moigne has synthesised and transformed hundreds of influences into a
unique system of thought, he would never claim ownership of it. Rather it
belongs to the systems community[3].
This theoretical construction will however, be labelled in the present text as
Le Moigne’s Systemic, or just LMS. This metaphor is used here mainly for
practical reasons but also because of the fact that the process of construction,
reconstruction and conjunction has clearly been done by Le Moigne himself.
2.3. An overview of LMS
The
present section gives an overview of LMS’ theories discussed in the rest of
this paper (see Figure 1). When discussing a theory of knowledge[4]
three main questions may be posed: What
is knowledge? - Le Moigne calls it a gnostic question - [A]; How to appreciate
the value of the knowledge, hence why
is knowledge valid? - Le Moigne calls it an ethical question - [B]; and How is knowledge constituted or engendered?
- Le Moigne calls it a methodological question - [C].[5]
(Le Moigne 1995b)
To
the question what is knowledge? [A],
LMS provides two basic hypotheses: the phenomenological hypothesis [A1] and the
teleological hypothesis [A2]. The first can be characterised by three
dominating properties: knowing is irreversible [A1a], recursive [A1b] and dialectic
[A1c]. The second question we shall discuss here, that is why is knowledge valid? [B], can be conceptualised on two levels.
First, the validation of knowing is postulated as due to the criterion of
projective feasibility [B1]. Secondly, the domain of science in general is postulated
to be autonomous [B2]. The third and final question discusses the
methodological aspects of how to
construct knowledge [C]. The answers to this can be conceptualised in three
groups: the first group, called here Modelling rationality [C1], includes
procedural rationality [C1a] rather than substantive, a conjunctive system of
logic [C1b] rather than the one of excluded thirds, and LMS’ own method [C1c]
rather than accepting Descartes’. The second group, called here Systemic
Modelling (SM), [C2], and which may be contrasted with the generally accepted
Analytical Modelling (AM), includes the following: a canonic model of a General
System (GS), [C2a], LMS’ basic modelling tool called Systemography (SGR),
[C2b], a theory of a General Process (GP), [C2c]. The latter is a foundation of
SM’s modelling tool for articulation of relations between processors in a
system; here it is called Teleological Complexification of Functional Levels
(TCFL), [C2d]. LMS offers also a paradigm of organisation, expressed in the
concept of Eco-Auto-Re-Organisation (EARO), [C2e]. This paradigm considers
organisation to be a property of a system. That property is a conjunction of
functions that is active and full of conflict, rather than just a passive
structure. The third group is the Theory of Inforgetics [C3], which focuses on
the relation between information and organisation, eventually mediated by a
decision. Inforgetics may be contrasted to the theory of energetics, the latter
focuses on the relation between matter and energy. Inforgetics offers the
Principle of Self-Organisation [C3a] and the Principle of Intelligent Action
[C3b]. These two may be juxtaposed with energetics’ principle of mutual
conservation between energy and matter (or entropy) and the principle of least
action (or maximum-from-minimum).
LMS
has also produced a certain number of applications, both on the meta or
epistemological level and on the object or theoretical level. The first one
includes: decision sciences epistemology of organisation, cognition sciences
epistemology of decision, epistemology of management sciences, cognition
sciences epistemology of intelligence symbolisation, epistemology of
communication sciences, epistemology of informatics or sciences of computation,
epistemology of technology or sciences of engineering, epistemology of design
sciences, and epistemology of education sciences (Le Moigne 1994b).
Secondly,
on the object level, LMS has been the foundation for Le Moigne and his colleagues
in research and theoretical construction in diverse areas. Le Moigne has mainly
but not exclusively developed theories for decision support and organisational
information systems, and organisational theory (Le Moigne 1973, 1974a, 1974b,
1975, 1981, 1983b, 1984a, 1985b, 1986a, 1986b, 1987a, 1992; Le Moigne &
Landry 1977a; Le Moigne & Carré 1977b; Le Moigne & Pascot 1979; Le
Moigne & Sibley 1986; Le Moigne & van Gigch 1989, 1990e; Le Moigne
& Bartoli 1997), among others. A sample of other’s applications include:
organisation information systems and software modelling (Bartoli 1991a; Quang
and Charter-Kastler 1991; Adreit 1994; Avenier 1996; Eriksson 1996); logistics
(Bartoli 1991b; 1994a; 1994b); group decision support systems (Orillard 1992);
organisational and business modelling; (Bartoli 1992; Vidal 1996); and
strategic management (Avenier 1992a; 1992b; 1995).
Figure
1.
Shows a principal overview of Le Moigne’s Systemics. The scheme is articulated
in three main domains; this is in accordance with the three basic questions
that characterise epistemological discussions: the assumptions of what is knowledge, the criteria of why knowledge is valid, and the
methodological instruments that support knowledge development, i.e. how to constitute knowledge.
3. The Epistemological Foundation
The
whole family of constructivist epistemologies as such share the anti-positivist
and anti-realist position. Some members of this family are: J. Piaget’s (1970)
dialectic constructivism, radical constructivism due to E. von Glaserfeld
(1995) and P. Watzlawick (1977, 1984), H. von Foerster’s (1984) second order
cybernetic constructivism, or G. Bateson’s (1971) pragmatist constructivism.
(Le Moigne 1993, 1995b) Le Moigne’s conception is labelled Projective Constructivist
Epistemology (PCE); this is due to the dominating teleological hypothesis (Le
Moigne 1995b). [6]
Further,
most epistemologies refer to a few basic hypotheses, often implicitly and in
different terms. The following presentation is done accordingly.
3.1. The phenomenological hypothesis[7]
”An
existing and knowledgeable reality may be constructed by its observers who are
then its constructors (or modellers).” (Le Moigne 1995b:39). In short, the
phenomenological hypothesis postulates that the knower knows a phenomenon only
due to artificial representations of subject-object interactions.
The
action of knowing does not start by the knowledge of self or by the knowledge
of things as such, but by that of their interactions. This interaction reflects
the inseparability of the act of knowing an object and the act of self-knowing,
as exercised by the knower. It is this cognitive interaction between the known
experience - rather than an ontic reality - and the knowing subject, which
forms - at the same time - the knowledge of the phenomenon and the knowledge of
the subject. Hence, the often used expression: intelligence organises the world
by organising itself (Le Moigne 1994, 1995b).
The
postulate that human beings know only inter-actions implies that knowing is an
active construction. The known reality is then a phenomenological reality
constructed by the subject due to her/his experiences in her/his neural system.
When the cogniser or knower knows only interactions and not the substances then
the knowledgeable reality is a reality of action. This reality is constructed
by a knower through symbolic interactions: schemes, letters, numbers, phonemes,
etc. (Le Moigne 1980a, 1995b).
Knowledge
is built up from the beginning by the subject and there are no givens, nor objective
empirical data or facts, nor innate categories or cognitive structures. The
initial argument is then of absolute primacy of the knower, capable of
attaching value to the knowledge that it constitutes. This knowledge then does
not have sense nor value outside the particular knower. Therefore, the knower
is not able to postulate the existence or not, of a knowable reality that is
strange to her/him. For the cogniser the unknown is only knowledge in the
instance of actualisation. Thus the metaphysical or theological question of eventual
unknown reality does not make sense for the knowing subject. (Le Moigne 1995b)
Further
LMS states: ”The experienced knowledge by a cognitive subject, whether it be tangible
or physically felt, or intangible or cognitively perceived, is knowledge if he
attributes it some proper value.” (Le Moigne 1995b:67). A value then, if it is
the subject’s own choice, can not be considered independent of the knowing
subject, which would be the value of objective truth. A knower’s value of
her/his knowledge is practice dependent for its appreciation of consequences of
actions that it elaborates when referring to this knowledge. In this case the
apparent simple criterion of objective truth - or revealed - proves to be less
appropriate when characterising knowledge (Le Moigne 1995b).
As a
consequence of this impossibility of objective knowledge, the question of
alternative criteria of validation emerges. Generally, constructivist
epistemologies associate themselves with the inter-subjective property of knowledge,
implying that mental schemes of different subjects may fit each other.
According to Le Moigne (1995b) however, this is the same as the American
pragmatist’s thinking of knowledge validation. This postulates the feasibility
criterion and expresses value in all knowledge. Le Moigne (1995b:68) gives the
following illustration: ”It is difficult to evaluate the objective truth of our
knowledge relative to human rights but one may reasonably consider that this
knowledge was less easily ‘teachable’ in the slavery ancient Greece than, for
example, during the American Secessionist War.” (The argument of validation
will be discussed further in the section 3.3.)
Finally,
the value attached to knowledge must be accessible somehow. This is exercised
through the artificial mediation of representations constructed by the subject
itself with the aid of a system of symbols, or to use Le Moigne’s (1995b:69)
expression: ”/.../ representation constructs knowledge which represents it.”
Then the problem posed to all paradigms, from realism to idealism, by the
significance of the correspondence between knowledge and representation is
given the phenomenological answer by PCE. Le Moigne (1995b:69) uses Korzybski
(1931-1980) to illustrate this argument in the following manner: ”The map - or
representation - is not the territory or a knowable reality independent of the
subject /.../”, rather ”/.../ the map expresses experimental knowledge of the
territory by the subject, which sometimes transforms it /.../”, therefore:
”/.../ if the map is not the knowable territory, the known territory becomes
the map.”. Le Moigne (1995b:44) summarises this as follows: ”We do not know reality
except through names or representations we attribute to individuals through
whom we perceive it. It might not be a ‘true’ reality which we know but an
artificial representation (names) that we associate with it.”. This
inseparability of knowledge and its representations as understood in their
inter-activity of intentional experience of the knowing subject and the subject’s
constructions that represent this phenomenological knowledge, is a basic hypothesis
of LMS.
The
following three sections will discuss the three dominating characteristics of
the phenomenological hypothesis: the irreversibility, the recursiveness and the
dialectics of knowing.
3.1.1. Time and irreversibility of knowing
The
irreversibility property postulates that knowledge is an action rather than a
result, knowing rather than knowledge. Such a notion refers to the Heraclitan
formula, stating that one cannot enter the same river twice... This quality
concerns the status of time relating to action; more precisely the
irreversibility of action. It may be contrasted with its antithesis due to classic
Newtonian mechanics, which presumed total reversibility of phenomena and time.
”The
absolute instantaneousness seems inconceivable to the knowing subject, because
he never had such a cognitive experience.” (Le Moigne 1995b:73). The concept of
action implies that the temporality that is perceived is irreversible. LMS uses
the works of Bergson, Costa de Beauregard and more recently Prigogine with
Stengers (1979), but also referring to R. Dubos (1981). The latter wrote a
little before he passed away: ”/.../ the time will come when one will realise
that the theory of rigidity of interior environment of C. Bernard is no longer
so valuable /.../ the scientists will realise that all changes are irreversible
/.../.” (in: Le Moigne 1987a:12).
3.1.2. Auto-reference, recursiveness and inseparability
of knowing
This
characteristic of knowing allows the knower to accept the cognitive act of
self-reference, forbidden since the Aristotelian logic of excluded thirds. LMS
reconsiders the notion when a proposition includes itself as a referent, due to
the works on living systems of Varela (1975, 1977) who builds on Spencer
Brown’s laws of form. Further, von Foerster’s (1959) and Bogdanov’s (1980)
works have clearly left their traces as well; the latter focuses on the
cognitive function of joining. (Le Moigne 1980a, 1985a)
The
recursiveness of cognition recognises the inter-dependence between the subject
and the object. This accounts for a case when an operand, in the same system
and at the same time, may also be an operator. LMS stresses that everyday
experience conforms that the human mind is capable of conjunctive reasoning as
well as of disjunctive reasoning. This expresses itself in grammar (verbal
substantive) and rhetoric in an intelligent way; for example, the concept of
organisation expresses, at the same time, the action and the result: an
organisation organises itself thus becomes (re-) organised. (Le Moigne 1990a)
3.1.3. The dialectics of knowing
The
dialectic property was well focused in the discussion of the phenomenological
hypothesis above. It concerns the interactionist paradigm: ”/.../ the emerging
system is both more and less than the sum of its elementary parts /.../” (Le
Moigne et al. 1992:10). Dialectics may be contrasted with and is a conjunction
of two alternative paradigms, the individualist or atomist and the holist
paradigms. The atomist considers the superiority of the individuals of a
particular system over the whole systems they are a part of. On the other hand,
the holist paradigm: ”/.../ considers that the fundamental explanation of a phenomenon
is to be found due to the action of the superstructure over the parts of the
system /.../” (Le Moigne et al. 1992:10). Hence, while the individualist
approach focuses on the diachronic property and the holist on the synchronic,
the interactionist stance manifests both. This was elegantly expressed already
by Pascal (1963:Thoughts no.72) ”/.../ I hold it equally impossible to know the
parts without knowing the whole and to know the whole without knowing the
parts.”
3.2. The teleological hypothesis
The
seminal article of N. Wiener, A. Rosenblueth and J. Bigelow (1943) ”Behaviour,
Purpose and Teleology” acted as a kind of catalyst for the epistemological
mediations, reintroducing the old thesis of teleology. The everyday experience
shows that the same cause do not always lead to the same effect, as was proclaimed
by Boudon (1968). The latter showed that there are four possible
correspondences and not one, between the occurrences of two sets of events: A
and B. Occurrences of B may in effect be rationally identifiable and interpretable
according to whether the occurrence of A is or is not necessary to it, and
whether it is or is not sufficient to it. In one correspondence A is a causal
one, hence a necessary and sufficient condition to B. While in the three others
it is not the case[8]
- ‘an acorn does not always cause an oak’. Thus Le Moigne (1977-1994:38) asks
whether they are: ”/.../ devoid of reason and not worthy of rational
knowledge?”
Attributing
to the knowing subject the decisive role in the construction of knowledge, the
phenomenological hypothesis takes into account the intentionality, or finality
(or aim, end, goal, objective, purpose, projectivity, aspirations...) of this
knowing subject’s mind. This meaning of the interpreted phenomenon is then
assigned in reference to one or more ends which in itself do not necessarily
impose or imply any ontological validity. Denying the free will of the knower,
the big-brother hypothesis of determinism seems less plausible to most cultures
today. The shadow is still visible of Kepler, Galileo and Newton’s imposed
conviction that the world is endowed of a structure and order, incorporating
cause-and-effect laws. (Le Moigne 1994)
In
summary, the two basic hypothesis of PCE, postulates that the knower knows only
intentional representations of dialectic inter-actions between experiences of
the subject and the subject itself. These are recursive and irreversible, and
constructed and organised actively by the knower. Hence PCE’s conception is
different from Piaget’s dialectic constructivism, which considers itself to be
an idealist-realist oscillation, even though it expressed the goal-oriented
property, seemingly in a teleonomic rather than in a teleological way. Table 1
illustrates the what-question of PCE.
PARADIGM: |
CONSTRUCTIVIST |
POSITIVIST
& REALIST |
|
1st
Gnostic hypothesis: |
Phenomenological |
Ontological |
|
|
characteristic
1: |
Temporal
irreversibility |
Total
reversibility |
|
characteristic
2: |
Included
thirds |
Excluded
thirds |
|
characteristic
3: |
Dialectic |
Individualist |
2nd
Gnostic hypothesis: |
Teleology |
Determinism |
Table
1.
Shows a juxtaposition of the basic hypothesis of what is knowledge. The
juxtaposed positions are the constructivist paradigm and the positivist and
realist paradigms. The two basic hypotheses of constructivist position and
their properties, may be also expressed in three cognitive properties, which
are: synchronicity, diachronicity and autonomy. These are well visible in the methodological arsenal of
Le Moigne’s Systemics.
3.3. The validity of knowing
The
issue of knowledge validation will be discussed on two conceptual levels; first
the validation of a particular statement and secondly the validation in terms
of the whole epistemic theory considered as a scientific domain. These two are
necessarily inter-related and support each other. The first theme has already
been discussed briefly in the discussion about the phenomenological hypothesis.
This kind of repetition manifests the recursivity of this theory.
3.3.1. From objective truth and the metaphysical
contract - To projective feasibility and the social contract
As
discussed previously, constructivist epistemologies in general postulate the
inter-subjective criterion for validation. It means that the mental schemes of
different knowers are to fit each other rather than match perfectly each other
or an ontic reality (see for example von Glaserfeld 1995). PCE however,
postulates that behind this reasoning the criterion of feasibility is to be
recognised. In this regard, LMS refers to the American pragmatist philosophy,
for example J. Dewey’s pragmatism (or instrumentalism) but also to Vico’s
(1710): ‘truth lies in the doing’. Given this, PCE postulates the criterion of
Projective Feasibility. It implies that truth is what the experiences of a
knower, or group of knowers, manifest as feasible due to their intentional
actions. This criterion is founded on the hypothesis of intentional and active
construction of knowing, preferably carried out with procedural reasoning (the
latter to be discussed in the following). That notion may be contrasted with
the criterion of objective truth, founded on the hypothesis of passive
reception of a given object, which is carried out with substantive reasoning.
(Le Moigne 1993, 1995b)
The
PCE may be asked for self-validation, especially while one of its main
properties is the self-referential quality. Le Moigne (1995b:40) delivers the
following reasoning. ”The power of the hypothesis of constructiveness of the
knowable reality stems from its plausibility and its effectiveness. Its
weakness, in the cultural context of the era, stems perhaps from its
de-sanctifying effect on scientific knowledge.” Hence, rather recursively, LMS
postulate that it is plausible or feasible to use the criterion of projective
feasibility. More specifically, for LMS to propose an epistemological
foundation and therefore criterion for knowledge construction implies a social
contract for the socio-cultural system that is supposed to develop this
knowledge. This knowledge ought to then hold some identifiable value for this
culture as expressed in sense, intelligibility or effectiveness (Le Moigne
1995b). The criterion of projective feasibility applies to the whole
epistemological foundation. On the other hand Le Moigne (1995b) notes that, if
this truth is an illusion, then the socio-cultural system does not accept any
more the criteria of knowing. This seems to be the case with positivist’s
conception of objective knowledge, in this case such an epistemological system
and its ethical value has no longer any basis. This is because: ”No scientific
or cultural authority could have the monopoly of determination of ethical value
of knowledge. But epistemology is best placed of all disciplines to recognise
and show questions on the value of knowledge, by which in some way, it ensures
the scientific status.” (Le Moigne 1995b:88). This social contract of epistemological
foundations is possible to exercise due to LMS’ notion of an autonomous science,
hence the epistemology may be ‘best placed’ to examine its own foundations. The
argument of scientific autonomy is discussed next.
3.3.2. From the science of autonomy to the autonomy of
science
In
the discussion above, LMS argues for the validity of an epistemological system
in reference to the social contract. Epistemology is postulated to be ‘...best
placed of all...’ to ensure its own foundations.
The
initial question is: ”Can science be understood enough to self-produce its own
foundations?” (Le Moigne 1983a, 1994:25). According to LMS, tackling this issue
exposes a paradox: while science in general can today speak of a particular
science of autonomy[9],
it still does not recognise the autonomy of the science in general. LMS blames
the positivist shadow for this situation. In order to manage this paradox LMS
twists the premise affirming the existence of the science of autonomy, and it
presents some criteria to recognise the domain of thought that may be called
science. LMS uses the following definition of autonomy: ”Property of a system
in general taking into account its aptitude to be identified and to identify itself,
at the same time, different and maintained different from its substrate environments,
on which it is interdependent.” (Le Moigne 1983a, 1994:29). This definition is
postulated to be recognised by physical, living and social sciences. According
to LMS, this notion of autonomy will make it possible to ensure an autonomy of
science.
Armed
with this conception, LMS goes on to examine the positivist notion of science.
The latter may be defined (Le Moigne 1983a, 1994:30) as: ”A set of types of
knowledge of studies, of universal value, characterised by a goal and a
predetermined method, and based on true, objective relations.” Hence in
positive terms, science may perhaps be identified as different from its
substrate (a subset of knowledge-types capable of differentiation of culture...).
But it could not identify itself as such (as an object of knowledge, it
precludes itself from being the subject of knowledge) and above all, it
precludes itself from maintaining its specific difference from the substrate
environment (the culture) because it wanted to assimilate, by successive
annexations, its substrate. Hence since Comte, science forbids itself to be
autonomous because of the postulation of previous determinants, that is
something can not be autonomous if it can not differentiate or identify itself.
(Le Moigne 1983a, 1994)
LMS
notes that the positivist tradition has attempted to escape from this
conception. Examples of this kind of succession from inside positive
epistemology are Popper’s (1959) ”Logic of Scientific Discovery”, which postulates
that a proposition may be scientific and false. Another attempt was due to T.
Kuhn’s theory of paradigms suggesting the relativity of epistemology.
LMS
on the other hand approaches the problem from another avenue. It associates
itself with Piaget’s (1967) classification of science, arguing that it is still
one of the most adequate. Piaget’s system suggests the forgotten paradigm of
the science of ingenium, more recently known as the science of design, the
science of artificial (Simon 1969), and for LMS the science of systems. The
science of design is considered as complementing or as an alternative to the
natural or analytical sciences. Armed with this notion, LMS draws the following
conclusion: ”Science thus understood does not uphold the ideal of an asymptotic
approach of some immanent truths (progress), it wants to be the edification by
humanity (design-construction) of its own natural state; nature for science
ceases to be a gift (natural) in order to become a work (artificial).” (Le
Moigne 1983a, 1994:38)
The
paradigm of design and therefore of organisation offers a liberating interpretation
of science: ”/.../ organisation of appearances by a system of principles /.../”
instead of ”/.../ revelation of laws /.../” (Le Moigne 1983a, 1994:39).
Organisation of appearances is then a characterisation of non-positive epistemology
where organisation - the fundamental paradigm - is a nucleus of all theories.
The organisation of appearances focuses on the organisation of perceptions;
perceptions that are both sensations and judgements because to feel is to
judge. ”To inform one self or to feel, is to decide to inform one self and
therefore to judge.” (Le Moigne 1983a, 1994:39) LMS considers science as an
organisation of perceptions and conceptions and therefore of knowledge.
LMS
draws attention to J. Ladriere’s (1975) definition of science that appreciates
its recursive and non-linear character: ”One could say that science is a
critical mode of knowledge. The qualifier ‘critical’ indicates on the one hand
that science exercises vigilant control over its own advances, on the other
hand that it works out methods that permit it to extend in a systemic fashion
its own field of knowledge. Scientific advances are at the same time reflexive
and prospective... The organising principles of science are not furnished to it
by external instances; the work-out of validity criteria and methods of
research intrinsically forms part of development of scientific knowledge.” (In:
Le Moigne 1983a, 1994)
Finally,
Le Moigne (1983a, 1994:40) modifies this conception in the following manner, science
is: ”/.../ a mode of critical knowledge at the same time reflexive and
prospective which ensures our resolution: that of scientific reality of
non-positive science. This suggests our thesis of autonomy of science, such an
understanding of science supports willingly the legitimacy of the science of
autonomy.” Table 2 shows a recapitulation of the validation discussion.
PARADIGM: |
REALIST & POSITIVIST |
PROJECTIVE CONSTRUCTIVIST |
Search for: |
Objective truth |
Projective feasibility |
Individual validity: |
Imposition of some ‘external’ criteria |
Subject’s believe (Subject’s coherence) |
Collective or social validity due to: |
Contract with Metaphysics or Religion |
Social contract (inter-subjective coherence/fit) |
Status of the scientific domain: |
Not autonomous |
Autonomous |
Table
2.
Shows a juxtaposition of validation criteria (the why-question) for the two respective positions, that is, the
constructivist paradigm and the realist and positivist paradigms.
4. LMS In Action
The
following sections will discuss the how-question of LMS theories. This issue is
determined fundamentally and necessarily by the two questions discussed
previously. Le Moigne has succeeded in formulating a significant number of
theories for modelling of complex systems. For reasons of clarity, the how of
LMS framework is articulated here in three categories: modelling rationality,
systemic modelling and inforgetic theory. These categories are not exclusive
but rather strongly interrelated.
4.1. Modelling rationality
The
domain of modelling rationality includes discussions on formalism and
procedural rationality, conjunctive logic and discussion of the method.
4.1.1. Formalism and procedural rationality
LMS
defines formalisation as: ”/.../ the cognitive exercise allowing an action (a
concrete system) to be transformed into a form (an abstract system) /.../)” (Le
Moigne 1993:4), while the reverse operation is considered interpretation. These
concrete and abstract systems are considered as systems of signs, eventually systems
of symbols. Consequently, formalism is defined as: ”/.../ a symbolic system of
rules carrying out such a process of transformation of experiences into
knowledge /.../. Formalism is therefore any system of signs resulting from
formalisation.” (Le Moigne 1993:4) This notion of formalism does not reduce
formalism to the traditional logical and mathematical formalism. LMS owes this
approach to Simon (1976b:304) who wrote: ”/.../ formal models which, however
rigorous, do not resemble very close the models using traditional mathematics.”
(Simon exemplifies the argument with the science of chemistry). Le Moigne
(1993:5) pursues with: ”The moralist, the jurist, the grammarian, the rhetor
and, sometimes, the poet, all know this form of ancestral experience.” Hence:
”/.../ rigour is understood as the reasoning process developed to an explicit
system of axioms, /.../ which are not necessarily those of deduction and
non-contradiction.” From this point of view, the three axioms of Aristotelian
logic - which shadow the occidental science (and are presented in the following
section on conjunctive logic) - are only one possible system of formal axioms
among others, not more or less rigorous. Le Moigne (1993) notes that even
Aristotle did not consider them to be imperative to reason.
In
contrast to the postulated neutrality of deductive logic, Simon (1973, 1976,
1977) took into account the infinite capacity of the multiple procedures that
the reason can construct, followed by eventual action. Le Moigne (1990a)
observes that Simon (1969) has shown in a convincing fashion, that from an
action a state can be deduced but not the reverse. Thus, LMS priors procedural
rationality that focuses deliberative, argumentative or dialectic heuristics.
In contrast, substantive rationality focuses on deductive, syllogistic or algorithmic
reasoning (Le Moigne 1977-1994, 1990a, 1993, 1995b, 1995c; Le Moigne &
Bartoli 1994). The procedural course allows mastering forms of reasoning that
were banned by deductive logic; such are: reflexiveness, recursiveness,
self-referentiality, irreversibility, trial and error experimentation, analogue
and dialectic reasoning through heuristic searches (Newell & Simon 1976).
This approach aims reasoning, first of all, to produce meaning rather than running
it by giving all emphasis to form. For example the system of musical notations
is ineffable, inexpressible and non modelable in the strict analytical or
substantive sense. LMS accepts the modesty of procedural reasoning that implies
an: ”/.../ absence of any universal criterion of ultimate validation other than
‘beliefs’ of the actor.” (Le Moigne 1993:10) Consequently, LMS adopts Simon’s
(1983) meta-heuristic: ‘searching is the end’, operationalised in heuristics of
trial-and-error experiments due to teleological models of successive and endless
transformations of representations. (Le Moigne 1993) This meta-heuristic
implies that the goal of human beings is to search for their goals and means of
being. Table 3 summarises this discussion.
PARADIGM: |
POSITIVIST & REALISM |
PROJECTIVE CONSTRUCTIVIST |
|
Preferred mode of rationality: |
Substantive reasoning |
Procedural reasoning |
|
|
characteristic 1 |
Syllogistic reasoning |
Rhetoric, Dialectic-Hybrid reasoning |
|
characteristic 2 |
Deduction |
Induction, Abduction, Transduction,
Retroduction[10] |
|
characteristic 3 |
Algorithmic reasoning |
Heuristic reasoning |
|
characteristic 4 |
Formal logic (OR-logic) |
Natural contemporary logic (AND-logic) |
Table
3.
Shows a juxtaposition of the reasoning rationality modes and some of its
characteristics, for the positivist and realist paradigms and the
constructivist paradigm, respectively. Characteristic four, that concerns the
respective paradigm’s system of logic, is presented more extensively in Table 4
below.
4.1.2. Conjunctive logic
As
suggested in the discussion on procedural reasoning, epistemological mediation
of LMS implies a reconsideration of the Aristotelian axiomatics, that is the
foundation of the formal disjunctive (OR) logic of excluded thirds. This logic
of excluded thirds has been culturally established by followers such as:
Boolean logic, Frege, Russell and Whitehead. According to Le Moigne (1977-1994)
reconsideration is crucial because: ”The only constraint that the theory
imposes on the modeller is the one of a prior verification: Had he shown some
axioms with which he will progressively support his inference and engrave his
design? But he should freely choose these axiomatics, and no theory will calculate
it for him.”. Before exposing LMS’ system of logic, a brief recounting of the
Aristotelian or disjunctive logic is given to make the argument more
intelligible. First is the axiom of identity: that which is, is: ‘A is A’.
Second, the axiom of non-contradiction: nothing may be and not be, at the same
time, hence: B may not be at the same time A and not-A. Third, the axiom of
excluded thirds: everything should either be or not be: B is either A or not-A.
This system of logic exclusively supports deductive reasoning. A problem arises
when a proposition includes itself as a referent. This issue has been a problem
since Aristotle, yet it has been ignored. Consequently, if A designates Truth,
the sign not-A should necessarily designate the opposite to Truth, that is:
False; and no other significance could be associated with the signs A and
not-A. This disjunctive logic (OR-logic) does not account for everyday phenomena
that humans experience in their complexity, as conjunctive. These are natural
because they are represented in everyday language by a number of concepts often
through verbal substantives. For example the concept of organisation may be
both a process and a state at the same time. (Le Moigne 1990a)
LMS
associates itself with works such as Korzybski’s (1931) proposition to
formulate a non-Aristotelian system of logic with the purpose of allowing
expressions of reasoning unconstrained by the axiom of excluded thirds. But
also with Varela’s (1977) work on autopoiesis, which requires a
self-referential epistemology and with Piaget’s proposed design of logic of
significations (Piaget & Garcia 1987).
The
generation of alternative systems is validated accordingly to the previously
exposed discussion, that is: ”There is not any immanent authority that shows
logicians and methodologists which are the good or true axioms. The formation
of a body of axioms of reference, is no doubt, a historic and cultural process.
One ascertains that these marks, which we will call axioms, were already used
in the past by some good minds who left us trails of their reflections.” (Le
Moigne 1990a:34)
LMS’
alternative, a conjunctive system of logic (also called: AND-logic or
self-referential logic) reflects the founding gnostic hypotheses and its
properties, as presented previously. The axioms of AND-logic are as follows.
First is the axiom of teleological operationality (or synchronicity). It implies
that a phenomenon is meaningful, if perceived as an intentional action and not
an erratic one. Second, the axiom of teleological irreversibility (or
diachronicity): a phenomenon that is capable of being modelled, hence meaningful,
is perceived as a transformation, forming a project in time, and having a
history. Third is the axiom of inseparability (or recursivity, or included
thirds, or autonomy). It axiomises that a phenomenon that is capable of being
modelled is perceived as inseparable knowledge of an operation and its product;
thus a product and a producer at the same time. (This is because the human
experience of an object and of itself is not separable, as the Cartesian shadow
imposed. For example organisation is considered both and at the same time to be
a state that is organised by human cognition and a process of organisation by
the same cognition). Table 4 summarises the discussion of LMS’ system of logic.
(Le Moigne 1977-1994)
PARADIGM: |
POSITIVISM
& REALISM |
CONSTRUCTIVISM |
|
System
of Logic: |
Analytic
logic |
Systemic
logic |
|
|
1st
axiom of: |
identity |
teleological
operationality |
|
2nd
axiom of: |
non-contradiction |
teleological
irreversibility |
|
3rd
axiom of: |
excluded
thirds |
inseparability |
Table
4.
Shows a juxtaposition of two systems of logic. That is, analytic logic (or
disjunctive logic, OR-logic, logic of excluded thirds) and systemic logic (or
conjunctive logic, AND-logic, logic of included thirds). They belong to the two
juxtaposed paradigmatic positions, that is, the positivist and realist paradigms
and the constructivist paradigm. The reader may observe the relation between axioms
of systemic logic and the three properties of cognition. That is to say, axiom
one and synchronity, axiom two and diachronity, and axiom three and autonomy.
4.1.3. Discussion of the method
The
traditional analytical approach to modelling seems to build its reasoning on
Descartes’ precepts - often implicitly. LMS’ alternative to analytical
modelling is systemic modelling. The latter is founded on its own precepts and which
will be reviewed in this section. In order to make LMS’ argument more
intelligible, Descartes’ four precepts will be briefly recalled. Descartes
first precept is: ”/.../ never to accept anything as true unless I evidently
know it to be such, that is to say, carefully avoid precipitation and prevention
and not to understand anything more in my judgement, than that which presented
itself so clearly and so distinctly to my mind, that I would not have any
occasion to doubt it.” The second precept is: ”/.../ to divide each of the
difficulties that I will examine, into as many parcels as they could be and as
could be required to better solve them.” The third precept is: ”/.../ to lead
my thoughts in order, starting with objects that are simplest and easiest to
know, to advance little by little, as if by degrees, to knowing of the more
compound ones and even assuming order between the ones that did not naturally
follow each other.” Finally, the fourth precept is: ”/.../ to make everywhere
such total enumeration and such general reviews that I could be ensured of
omitting nothing.” (In: Le Moigne 1977-1994:30)
It
seems that if these precepts would be applied to themselves, a doubt may
emerge. On the precept of evidence, a question may be posed: are there many proclaimed
proofs that are doubtless? The first precept of LMS is then of pertinence:
”Agree that all objects that we consider define themselves in relation to
implicit or explicit intentions of the modeller and to never forbid ourselves
from doubting this definition, if in modifying our intentions the perception we
have of these objects also changes.” (Le Moigne 1977-1994:43). For example:
”The equal sign does not have the same significance for the mathematician
writing 2 + 2 = 4 and for the programmer writing N = N + 1 but for each of them
this sign is pertinent in relation to their project of the moment.” (Le Moigne
1977-1994:33). Thus a question of importance would be: ‘What do we intend?’
Secondly, concerning Descartes’ reductionist precept, many thinkers since the
Aristotelian precept, ‘the whole is more than the sum of its parts’ have expressed
a similar concern. For example, taking apart a car in Great Britain is not
sufficient to gain understanding why its steering wheel is on the right side,
because the reason for this lies outside this system; hence the examination requires
a systemic or conjunctive approach. Descartes’ hypothesis of a closed system is
replaced with the one of an open system: ”To perceive the object already as an
inserted, immersed, active part in a greater whole /.../ and to make the
intelligence of this environment, the condition of our knowledge of the
object.” (Le Moigne 1994a:34). Interactionist precept is the second of LMS:
”Always consider the object to be known by our intelligence as an integral and
active part of a greater whole. Perceive it first globally, in functional
relation with its environment without worrying about establishing a faithful
image of its internal structure, where existence and uniqueness are never considered
given.” (Le Moigne 1977-1994:43). Thirdly, on Descartes’ causalist precept, the
previous discussion about the teleological hypothesis accounts very well for
Descartes’ inadequacy. Moreover LMS states: ”We will not cease being rational
because we will consider other hypotheses on the ends, no longer wired in the
structure but perhaps programmed and multiple in some memories even programmable
and inventable in recourse to some form of imagination. For the explanation
cause-and-effect, intelligence substitutes through a fertile generalisation,
the interpretation (or understanding) behaviour-end.” (Le Moigne 1977-1994:39).
Hence, the teleological precept of LMS states: ”/.../ interpret the object
through its behaviour not through itself, without first searching to explain
its behaviour through some law implied in an eventual structure. Understand on
the other hand its behaviour and the recourses it commands in relation to
projects that the modeller freely attributes to the object. Consider the
identification of these hypothetical projects a rational act of intelligence
and agree that their demonstration will be rarely possible.” (Le Moigne
1977-1994:43). In this manner, LMS propagates that teleology expresses itself
through signs (and their manipulations) to be compared with Descartes’ notion
where causes are expressed through laws. Consequently, the question should not
be of the intrinsic laws of a structure’s behaviour, rather asking for explicit
intentions that the behaviour should be referred to (Le Moigne 1977-1994).[11]
Discussing the fourth and final precept of Descartes that is about an exhaustive
search, a question emerges: Is it possible or practical to do such an exhaustive
enumeration? This for example, when the concern is a socio-economic model
manifesting thousands of relations between variables? Instead, LMS asks the
modeller to omit a lot deliberately - with some risk of failure - and proposes
aggregates - more modestly but also openly. This selects what is interesting in
relation to the modeller’s goals. LMS’ precept of aggregativity states then:
”Agree that all representation is partisan, not through the forgetfulness of
the modeller, but deliberately. In consequence, research recipes capable of
guiding the selection of aggregates considered pertinent and exclude the
illusionary objectivity of an exhaustive enumeration of elements to consider.”
(Le Moigne 1977-1994:43). Table 5 summarises the method under discussion.
Finally,
LMS exercises the validity of its method in the same pragmatic fashion as defined
previously: ”The axiom body is neither true, nor false. It only matters to us
that it is not totalitarian. One wanted only to underline the fact that it is
possible to propose competing axioms.” (Le Moigne 1977-1994:44).
The discussion of the method: |
Descartes’ analytical method |
LMS systemic method |
|
|
1st precept of: |
evidence |
pertinence |
|
2nd precept of: |
reduction |
interaction |
|
3rd precept of: |
causality |
teleology |
|
4th precept of: |
exhaustivity |
aggregation |
Table
5.
Shows a juxtaposition of two methods for conduction of good reason. That is,
Descartes’ method that represents the analytical approach of the positivist and
realist paradigms, and Le Moigne’s method that represents the systemic approach
of the constructivist paradigms.
4.2. Systemic Modelling and its instruments
Systemic
Modelling (SM) is used here as a label for a set of cognitive modelling instruments
that LMS offers the modeller. While SM’s domain of inquiry is a complex system,
it may be juxtaposed with Analytical Modelling (AM), whose domain of inquiry is
a complicated system (Le Moigne 1990a, 1977-1994).
The
exposition will start with a discussion of some central concepts, namely:
complexity, modelling and system. This will be followed by a presentation of
some modelling instruments, such as: General System (GS), Systemography (SGR),
General Process (GP), Information Processing System (IPS), Teleological Complexification
of Functional Levels (TCFL), the Decision-Information-Operation System model
(DIOS) and the Eco-Auto-Re-organisation paradigm (EARO).
4.2.1 Complexity and modelling
”The
notion of complexity implies a possible and plausible yet unpredictable
emergence of a new sense inside a phenomenon, that one considers as complex.”
(Le Moigne 1990a:3). LMS’ notion of a complex system implies per definition
that it is irreducible to a single finished model. This system may be complicated
or not, sophisticated or not, composed of many components and interactions or
not, but it is complex. Then complexity is the attributed quality that is
deliberately considered by a subject’s mind in its perception or conception of
something that exercises unpredictable emergent behaviour.[12]
”And no tribunal is empowered to confer patents of ontological complexity.” (Le
Moigne 1990a:4). SM’s approach admits its modesty in being satisfied with making
phenomena intelligible but it does not necessarily explain them. Le Moigne
(1990a) points out, by examining the etymological roots of “complex” which
originates in plexus, that complex is not opposite to simple but rather to
implex. This notion of complexity may be considered in contrast to analytical
modelling’s approach which, due to its epistemological foundations, is potent
to deal with complicated systems (i.e. systems that can be explained), not with
complex systems.
The
next issue is modelling. It is considered as: ”An action: of elaboration and
intentional construction through symbols of models, of making intelligible a
phenomenon perceived as complex and to amplify the reasoning of an actor deliberately
intervening inside the phenomenon aiming to predict consequences of his project
of possible actions.” (Le Moigne 1990a:5). In other words, modelling implies
intentional representation by symbols, it implies conception and design. The
subject knows its objects through such a designation of symbols to these
objects. Further, these symbolic constructions may be reasoned and manipulated
in order to infer deliberate meaning, which may be followed by a conception of
new possible behaviour. Systemic modelling is necessarily projective or
teleological modelling (TM), perfectly reflecting the two gnostic hypotheses
and their properties. Further, TM implies that a model of a system is
necessarily recursive because it is established in an interaction between the
modeller and the modelled phenomenon conceived as complex. TM implies that a
model is a conjunction of the symbols or representation, of the modeller and
its intention and of the modelled experience that is under consideration. (Le
Moigne 1984d, 1990a, 1990c). The model cannot be separated from the modeller’s
action, as is postulated by AM - in its attempt to reach neutrality. This
implies the shift from AM’s objectivity to SM’s projectivity. The constructed
model is always characterised by a modeller’s capacity to clarify modelling
finality or finalities, in other words of self-finalisation. Consequently, the
prime question for SM is: What is the problem? rather than: How to solve the
problem? – as is the case with AM. SM re-focuses the attention from AM’s
frequent mono-criterion approach to multi-criteria management.[13]
SM’s projectivity exposes AM’s dilemma, that is the unconditional obedience of
natural laws, i.e. cause-and-effect relation, which reduces finality or
intention to determinism. Determinism makes AM impotent when, for example, the
laws are not known or the problems do not state themselves clearly - both
situations are common in the domain of complex systems. While AM simplifies,
reduces and analyses its phenomenon of concern, SM deliberately conceives and
complexifies its consideration. Simplification of a complex phenomenon destroys
its intelligibility. (Le Moigne 1990a & 1977-1994) Table 6 presents a
mnemonic palette of some concepts associated with AM and SM, respectively.
MODELLING MODE: |
ANALYTIC MODELLING |
SYSTEMIC MODELLING |
Domain of concern: |
Complicated Systems |
Complex Systems |
Characteristics of the studied phenomenon: |
Object (State) |
Project (Process) |
|
Element (Substantive) |
Active entity (Verb) |
|
Control |
Intelligence (Knowledge) |
Notion of system: |
S = (Things, Relations), (a Set) |
General System, (to be, to do, to become) |
Notion of organisation: |
Structure of passive states |
Conflictful conjunction of three recursive
actions. The actions are: to produce and self-produce,
to relate and self-relate, to maintain and self-maintain |
Mode of study: |
Analysis |
Design (Conception) |
|
Simplification |
Complexification |
|
Causal explanation, (cause-effect study;
determinative natural laws) |
Teleological comprehension, (means-end study;
finalisation of phenomenon) |
Notion of model: |
Disjuncted simplification of reality |
Conception or perception of phenomenon; a
conjunction of a representation (model), the modeller and the modelled |
Primary questions of study: |
What are the determinants? What is it made
of? |
What is the goal? What does it do? |
|
Efficacy (How-to-do?) |
Effectivity (What-to-do?) |
Validation: |
Evidence (objective truth) |
Pertinence (projective/cognitive feasibility) |
Table
6.
Shows a juxtaposition of some general modelling concepts. The two modelling
palettes belongs to analytical modelling of positivist and realist paradigms,
and to systemic modelling of constructivist paradigm, respectively. The reader
may observe the relation between the concepts of systemic modelling and the
three states of cognition. This is clearly manifested in the notion of General
System, that will be discussed bellow. Hence, to be or autonomous, to do or synchronic and to become or diachronic.
4.2.2 The genesis of modelling paradigms and the
General System
At
the heart of LMS is the theory of General System. The history of science has
generated five main canonical models for guiding the modelling process. The
following discussion will briefly review this evolution, ending with the
canonic model of a General System, which is the kernel of General Systems
Theory. (Le Moigne 1976a, 1976b, 1977c, 1977-1994, 1990a, 1995b)
The
first modelling paradigm is rational mechanics. It was finally established at
the end of 19th century and perfectly reflected the Cartesian
imposition. All objects were supposed to be explained by focusing on the
structure that in turn was believed to determine the function. This notion was
founded on the assumption of full reversibility, where cause-and-effect was supposed
to be explained by mechanics. Lord Kelvin may very well be considered one of
its main ambassadors.
The
second paradigm is statistical mechanics or thermodynamics, due to L.
Boltzmann. It established itself as a reaction to rational mechanics. It
postulated the inadequacy of ‘studying the moon with a microscope’. Statistical
mechanics re-focused the attention from structure-function to
structure-evolution, or from kinematics to kinetics. Evolution or dynamics took
into account the irreversible transformations of internal structure over time,
yet of a closed system.
The
tension of the two modelling paradigms was elegantly dealt with by W. Weaver’s
(1948) problems of: simplicity (rational mechanics), disorganised complexity
(statistical mechanics) and unmanageable organised complexity.[14]
This tension allowed the modeller to leave the Cartesian shadow. In search for
a unified avenue two new modelling paradigms emerged: the structuralist[15]
paradigm that is more European and the cybernetic paradigm that is more North
American.
Hence,
the third modelling paradigm is the structuralist approach. J. Piaget (1968)
may be seen as one of its main ambassadors. He considered it to be a method
that describes an object in its totality, that is to say, one that is at the
same time both functioning and evolving; hence simultaneously synchronic and diachronic
or structured and structuring. This mortal blow to reductionism of the two
previous modelling approaches recognised that the character of totality
belonging to structures comes of itself. A structure is formed due to the elements
but these are, at the same time, subordinate to the structure. For example, a
human being (here an element) is affected by the culture of a society (here a
structure) that she/he is part of; the structure is however affected (constructed,
maintained…) by the individual, at the same time. This approach clearly exposed
the limitations of causalism employed in mechanics. It limited itself however
by presupposing an automatic structure, then it led itself to a dead end by
modelling closed systems, as discussed above in the two previous mechanical approaches
of modelling.
The
fourth modelling paradigm is the second attempt to overcome the problem of
mechanical modelling. Cybernetic modelling offers an inverted modelling
approach of the structuralist notion. Instead of centring the modeller’s attention
on mechanism’s or organism’s structures, it proposed closing them in a black
box, favouring interpretation of the behaviour, that is, a conjunction of
function and evolution. The behaviour of a black box is to be interpreted in
reference to its goal(s) and environment. The classic cybernetic approach of
Wiener et al. (1943) and McCulloch et al. (1943) became very powerful after the
introduction of the concept of informational feedback. Cybernetics did not
attempt to explain the mechanisms in a system. It rather attempted to
understand or interpret a system’s behaviour in permanent reference to its
projects. This is described in relation to the environment inside which it behaves.
For example, in cybernetics terms a polar bear is: something (a black box) that
tries (behaviour) to survive (goal) in the Arctic area (environment). Modes of
cybernetic modelling, however, often stumbled on the difficulty of accounting
for the duality inside the same model. This property was what the structuralists
attempted to emphasise, that is, the simultaneous taking account of functioning
and evolving. The cybernetic characterisation of a polar bear may indeed very
well apply to an Eskimo also.
The
integration of these two paradigms, the structuralist and the cybernetic,
established the systemic paradigm in the middle of 1970’s (Le Moigne
1977-1994). Hence, LMS’ definition of the canonical model as a general system
(GS) is: something (a structure) that is functioning and transforming toward a
goal in an environment. Derived from the GS, the experience shows that a
perceived phenomenon may be defined due to three poles or perspectives. First,
the morphological, anatomical or analytical, is the static representation of
substance and its composition. Secondly, the functional, physiological,
praxiological, sometimes experimental, is the action of a system in its
environment. Thirdly, the morphogenetical, genetic/teleological, transformational,
dynamic, evolutionary or historical, accounts for a phenomenon’s
transformations in time toward some goals. Hence a phenomenon may also be
defined as: to be, to do and to become. (Le Moigne 1990a, 1977-1994). Table 7
shows a juxtaposition of the discussed modelling paradigms.[16]
Modelling
Paradigm |
Essential
qualities |
|
||||
Rational
Mechanics: |
function |
--- |
structure |
closed |
Determinative |
|
Statistical
Mechanics: |
--- |
transformation |
structure |
closed |
Determinative |
|
Structuralism: |
function |
transformation |
structure |
closed |
Determinative |
|
Cybernetics: |
behaviour |
--- |
open |
Teleological |
||
Systemics: |
function |
transformation |
structure |
open |
Teleological |
|
Table
7.
Shows a juxtaposition of the five fundamental modelling paradigms and its
essential qualities. These are the result of scientific inquiry of the
Occidental civilisation. Systemic modelling, which is Le Moigne’s position,
represents the richest model.
4.2.3. Systemography, Genotype and Phenotype
LMS
stresses that General System Theory is a theory of modelling rather than a
general theory of models (Le Moigne 1977-1994); this is in accordance to the
constructivist foundation. LMS’ tool for modelling then, is called Systemography
(SGR). It may be recognised in analogy to photography or biography. ”Systemography
is a procedure with which one constructs models of phenomena perceived as
complex, representing it deliberately as and through a general system.” (Le
Moigne 1977-1994:28). The mode of usage of this cognitive instrument is the
following: an observer, e.g. the representation system, constructs at the same
time an isomorphy[17]
of the GS and a homomorphy[18]
of the phenomenon to be represented. Verification of the isomorphical relation
will not be problematic because of the GS definition given above. The
homomorphical models, on the other hand, will not produce any perfect relational
model as conceived in positivism. Similar to photography, it is possible to
make many systemographies of a phenomenon. The result of systemography may only
be validated due to their projective feasibility. Further, the role of a
modeller should be explicated, especially her/his project. When modelling of
the perceived or conceived entity is exercised then the modeller should
systemograph itself or become systemographed at the same time, this in order to
make the systemographed entity more intelligible. Finally, in accordance with
the triangular definition of GS: functional, organic and historic, systemography
may be used in three modes: conception or design, analysis and simulation. (Le
Moigne 1977-1994, 1990a).[19]
LMS
makes use of J.P. Dupuy’s (1986) conception of genotype and phenotype.[20]
These manifest the usage of systemography. The genotype or the canonic model of
GS that is an artificial construction of human mind, together with the modeller
establishes one or many potential phenotypes of the phenomenon perceived or conceived
as complex. The genotype is both a matrix and a rule: ”Matrix is a model in
general or paradigm /.../: a model of an organisation or of complex
teleological actions; a rule (or syntagm), a procedure of construction, by homomorphism
of models which are phenotypes of the phenomenon considered by the model
builder.” (Le Moigne 1993:13)
4.2.4. The General Process
”The
representation of a phenomenon, perceived as complex by a system, rests on an
explicit hypothesis of irreversible rationality, teleological and recursive.”
(Le Moigne 1990a) As earlier discussed SM models active systems where the
inquiry focuses on the action of a system, both synchronic and diachronic,
rather than on its state. Such an action is represented by a symbolic
processor. This notion may be expressed well through the canonic model of a
general process (GP), processed by one or many processors. ”A process is
defined by its exercise and its result /.../. A process exists when there is a
change in position of space-form reference in time, of a collection of some
products, identifiable by their morphology - their form.”[21]
(Le Moigne 1990a:46). Hence, the genotype of a process represents a conjunction
of temporal transfer or in other words a function of time, space and form.
Further, all systems may be represented as multiple actions or entanglement of
processes - this is in accordance with the general system that is conceived as
a composition of multiple processors.
4.2.5. Information Processing System
In
order to make the reason for LMS’ use of Information Processing System paradigm
more intelligible, a brief return to the notion of a complex system is
necessary.
A
complex system must by definition be a system that manifests a certain degree
of autonomy. This is because if a system’s behaviour was to be completely
dependent on exogenous interventions, over which it would not have any influence,
it would then not be a complex system. On the contrary, it would be a
completely predictable system, a programmable automaton, whose programme would
completely define its predictable behaviour. In contrast, complexity appears
and develops completely with the emergence of the capacity of autonomy inside a
system. Hence, behaviours are elaborated by the system itself in an endogenous
manner. A complex autonomous system is necessarily open to its environment.
This both incites and constrains it, hence the system and its environment are
trans-acting. The system is then both autonomous and open, therefore partially
dependent - a paradox for the positivist notion. This is possible when a system
has its own projects for the guidance of its behaviour, which in turn requires
intelligence. Intelligence of a complex system is then defined as: a system’s
”/.../ capacity to elaborate and conceive its own behaviours in an endogenous
or internal fashion.” (Le Moigne 1990a:81). The behaviours of a complex system
are adaptive, which implies intentional responses to what the system perceives
as solicitations of the environment. Consequently, this invention capacity of
self-finalised action takes into account the complexity of a system, because it
makes intelligible - not necessarily explicable - the emergence or appearance
of an adaptive, non-pre-programmed behaviour. This description may be
summarised in the following hypothesis: a complex system is an autonomous
system, which is an intelligent system and therefore an adaptive system. (Le
Moigne 1990a)
SM
uses the Information Processing System (IPS), conceived by Newell and Simon
(1972), as a modelling procedure of complex systems. Such a modelling approach
is required to give account of a complex system’s capacity to elaborate its own
projects and actions, at the same time. This capacity aims to adapt the system’s
behaviour to its goals, therefore the system’s organisation of its goals.
Hence, SM makes use of IPS’ potential to represent the behaviour of such an
organisation by symbolic manipulation. The canonic model of the IPS represents
a conjunction of three fundamental functions: a communication system, a computation
system and a memorisation system.[22]
(Newell & Simon 1972, Le Moigne 1990a) ”This canonic form of IPS
constitutes a theory, or a plausible general model, of organisation of a
complex system, capable of self-organisation /.../”, therefore: ”The method of
representation of a complex system through the system of processing of
information symbols, which is presumed to account intelligibly for its behaviours,
proves easy to implement in a number of exercises of practical modelling.” (Le
Moigne 1990a:82-83).
4.2.6. Teleological Complexification of Functional
Levels
”Nothing
is less simple than the interrelation between two processors!” (Le Moigne
1990a:52). According to LMS, an active entity becomes a system when two or more
processors, which constitute the system, may be distinguished by its observer.
Further Le Moigne (1990a) shows that a system consisting of two processors is
capable of establishing as much as sixteen endogenous interrelations, including
the feedback relations. This implies potentially sixteen different behaviours
of the system.[23]
The inter-relation of N processors or network of processors will rapidly
complexify the modeller’s perception. Such complexification makes often new
behaviour emerge, which is rarely predictable through linear computing, hence
counter-intuitive. This challenge of the observer’s cognitive limitations asks
for help. SM employs an instrument that has the intention to make such
situations intelligible, yet not necessarily to explain them. It builds on
Simon’s (1969) hypothesis of a projective functional complexification. This
cognitive instrument is labelled here: Teleological Complexification of
Functional Levels (TCFL). TCFL in turn builds on two basic hypotheses: the teleological
hypothesis and the hypothesis of sub-systems. Operationally, it implies that
when a high number of processors comprise a system of interest, which is a
common situation in complex systems, human cognitive limitation is then challenged
easily. Experience has shown however, that such a variety also leads to certain
regularities. It is therefore often possible to observe enough dense
subsystems, regularities or patterns. This quality of a complex system makes it
quasi-articulable. This implies that it is possible to articulate a system’s
subsystems and their interrelations in reference to goal(s). This shows that
while the amount and complexity of endogenous interrelations in a subsystem is
great, the reverse may be said of its exogenous interrelations, which are
therefore intelligible. (Le Moigne 1990a). When referring to the projects, it
is then possible to deliberately arrange the functional levels into a system of
processors and therefore of symbols:[24]
”/…/ as a composer deliberately seeks to compose a musical system with the aid
of symbolic representation. In other words, modelling complex systems will be organised
in a series of iterations between projects and symbolic representations which a
modeller constructs of them.”[25]
(Le Moigne 1990a:54).
4.2.7. Decision-Information-Operation System model
Following
the argument of TCFL, LMS has presented a general and a priori identification
of pertinent levels of complexification, in order to organise a model of a
complex system. This notion is an instrument to be used by a modeller when
approaching a complex system with the need of articulation of its subsystems
and their interrelations, in order to make the complex phenomenon intelligible.
However, LMS emphasises that such identification is much more difficult than,
for example, the establishment of the General System genotype. The functional
model is called: Decision-Information-Operation-System (DIOS). The
identification of this model has not only been due to the TFCL-tool but also to
the work of K. Boulding’s (1956) nine level system,[26]
the GS genotype, Simon’s model of decision making and PCE’s basic hypotheses
(Le Moigne 1990). The elaboration process of DIOS is presented in Le Moigne
(1977-1994, 1990a). Here however, only the results will be briefly sketched.
LMS presents two modes of DIOS. The first and more general one is due to a six
level articulation, resulting in three subsystems. While the second mode is
more elaborated, due to a nine level articulation, it results in five subsystems.
The
first mode is comprised of: the Decision System (DS), the
Information-Memorisation System (IS) and the Operation System (OS). In this
case, the DS makes decisions for the whole system, the IS memorises information
and acts as a coupling or communication between the DS and the OS, while the OS
does the work in the system. This may be compered with the traditional
cybernetic system, the Decision-Operation-System (DOS) model, which is comprised
of two subsystems, the DS and the OS. Indeed, one of the main arguments of LMS
is that of the better adequacy of the systemic model compared to the cybernetic
one. The systemic model, the DIOS, is supposed to perfectly reflect the phenomenological
hypothesis: ‘we know only the representations of the interactions…’. At the
same time, accordingly to LMS, the cybernetic model (the DOS) reduces complex
systems to automata, which manifest a complicated yet predictable behaviour.
This is due to the cybernetic command-control relation that imposes the will of
the DS on the OS. The OS acts in perfect accordance with the commands, not
manifesting any divergence. In the systemic conception such a relation between
DS and OS is of a complex nature, hence expressed in the memorisation system.
Further, the cybernetic system lacks memory, this reduces complexity to a
simple thermostat, while the memory of the DIOS expresses the potentiality of a
system and accounts for the temporal quality, hence its diachronicity. This is
considered to be necessary for a complex system in order to be able to handle
or manage the environment’s unpredictable variation and complexity (Le Moigne
1990a).
The
second mode, a little more elaborate, expresses all nine levels of Boulding’s
proposition. Starting from the first mode of DIOS, its DS is recursively
comprised of three subsystems. These are in accordance with Simon’s model of
decision making.[27]
The DS consists of the Co-ordination System (CS), which co-ordinates the
numerous actions exercised in the operating system. Next is the Imagination System
(IMS) that designs new forms of actions. Finally, the Self-finalisation System
(FS) manifests the teleological quality of a complex system. It establishes the
gap between the perceived and projected situation. Hence, the second mode of
DIOS comprises the operation system, the information-memorisation system, the
co-ordination system, the imagination system and the self-finalisation System
(Le Moigne 1990b).
Although
Le Moigne never states so, DIOS’ second mode may be very well juxtaposed with
Stafford Beer’s (1979, 1981) Viable System Model (VSM). VSM is founded on the
traditional cybernetic model, the DOS, together with neurobiological studies of
human beings. In its elaborated form VSM comprises five subsystems, as the DIOS
does. These are the operating system, the co-ordination system, the control
system, the intelligence system and the policy system. For an overview of this
discussion see table 8.
PARADIGM: |
CYBERNETIC
|
SYSTEMIC
|
1st mode: |
Decision, Operation: System (DOS) |
Decision, Information, Operation: System (DIOS) |
2nd mode: |
Policy, Intelligence, Control, Co-ordination,
Operation (according to Viable System Model) |
Finalisation, Imagination, Co-ordination, Memorisation, Operation |
Table
8.
Shows a juxtaposition of the cybernetic and systemic approaches to an a priori
model of a complex system. In the cybernetic notion, mode one represents a
direct relation between the observed and the observing system, while in the
systemic notion such a relation is complex, hence represented by an
intermediate memorisation system. The latter manifest the phenomenological
hypothesis as presented before in the what
is knowledge discussion (we know only representations of interactions between
the mind and the phenomenon). Mode two presents the two paradigm’s articulation
of the observing system. In the cybernetic position, it is due to S. Beer’s
Viable System Model, as generated by biological studies of the neural system.
While in the systemic position, the articulation is due to H.A. Simon’s psychological
studies of human decision making process.
4.2.8. The paradigm of organisation
The
implication of the previous discussions is, that in order to conceive or
perceive a complex system, it is necessary to postulate some strong basic
hypothesis. This is recognised by PCE. For example, in designing or identifying
a complex system, it is necessary to explain projects through which it is
known. The expression of a complex system embodies: the modelled experience,
the modeller that is experiencing and the model that represents these two. This
inseparability implies an action of organisation of representations, which
results in an organisation. SM’s notions of organisation is a conjunction of
the action and the result, which passes through a central concept of active
organisation. In the quest for active organisation, LMS has inherited and
modified Morin’s (1977) concept of organis-action. Hence, organis-action is:
”/…/ a property of a complex system, allowing at the same time to account for
behaviour of each projective level, which we attribute to the system, and of
the expression between these levels, without separating them.” (Le Moigne
1990a:74). Le Moigne modified Morin’s formula of the active organisation by
adding to it the recursive property (Le Moigne 1985a). Hence, the postulated
paradigm of organisation is: Eco-Auto-Re-Organisation (EARO). It manifests the
observer’s cognitive action when perceiving and conceiving phenomena, as
expressed in the basic hypotheses of PCE. Figure 2 illustrates EARO paradigm
briefly.
Figure
2.
Shows the fundament of systemic conception of the Eco-Auto-Re-Organisation
paradigm. This is the foundation for the notion of an active organisation (or
organis-action). The reader may note the relation between this model and the
three properties of cognition, that is to say: eco- is synchronic, auto- is autonomous, and re- is diachronic. Hence, the concept of an
active organisation manifest the capability of a cognitive system, that is, of
an observing system that organises its perceptions and conceptions which results
is an active organisation.
Founded
in EARO-paradigm, LMS proposes a canonic model of an active organisation, i.e.
organis-action (see Figure 3). This aims and permits to support the
representation of a complex of actions, which needs to be taken into account
when modelling complex systems (Le Moigne 1990a). The active organisation genotype
describes the property of a general system, that is capable at the same time of
the conflictful (Le Moigne 1986b) conjunction of three recursive functions.
These functions include: maintaining and self-maintaining (time-action), linking
and self-linking (space action), and producing and self-producing
(form-action).[28]
The active organisation is thus a conjunction of itself and its environment.
This means that it is, at the same time, inseparable and dependent on its
environment. It is capable of differentiating from its environment due to the
autonomy of a modeller’s perception. Such a conjunction could not be possible
without a foundation in conjunctive logic. The conjunction of the actor and his
action has been expressed by Morin as follows: ”To conceive the principle of complexity,
it is not sufficient to associate the antagonistic ideas in a concurrent and
complementary way. The very character of the association also has to be considered:
Organisation that transforms each of the terms in the process of looping.”
(Morin 1977:381)
LMS’
concept of an active organisation may be contrasted with AM’s concept of
organisation. The latter notion implies a passive and invariable structure of
states, perfectly founded in the disjunctive logic. On the other hand, an
active organisation’s conjunction of actions expresses the duality of action
and result, as founded in conjunctive logic. Active organisation is organised
and organising in irreversible gestalts, stable enough to be distinguished by
the knower that perceives or conceives it. (Le Moigne 1990a) See table 6 for a
juxtaposition of the two notions of organisation.
Figure
3.
Shows the canonic model of an active organisation as founded in the
Eco-Auto-Re-Organisation paradigm. This model is conceived as a conflictful
conjunction of three recursive functions: link and self-link (space or
communication function), maintain and self-maintain (time or memory function),
produce and self-produce (form or computation function).
4.3. The Inforgetic paradigm
Due
to the energetic model, the classical conception of organisation implies an
arrangement of a network of stable organs, which optimise a global process of
conversion of materials into energies (Le Moigne 1990a). The domination of
positivism in science made physicalism and energetics the measure of all
scientific knowledge. The postulate was that a good scientific discipline ought
to have the reference model of mathematical physics. The energetic paradigm
studies all processes of change of matter into energy and energy into matter, a
process which is first identified then quantified. The inadequacy of the
postulated extension of this notion to the science of mind and the social
sciences became untenable, for example, when considering measuring a quantity
of information with the help of a unit, a bit, which does not equate to any
dimension (Le Moigne 1991a, 1997). (The argument of information will be developed
more in the section that discusses information and self-organisation below).
Hence, LMS associates itself with Bateson’s critique of borrowing
insufficiently ensured concepts as well as borrowing the supporting epistemological
references, when the field of study is changed. ”To consider social
organizations as energetic phenomena and to interpret them in terms of energetic
theory is pure nonsense.” (Bateson 1972:198). Social organisations, like
businesses and families, ought not to be considered first of all as processes
of interaction between matter and energy, as the energetic paradigm suggested.
Rather they should be considered as processes of conceptual interaction between
information and organisation mediated by the decision of an intelligence. (Le
Moigne 1990a)
LMS
proposes an alternative paradigm to energetics, namely the inforgetic paradigm.
The latter perfectly reflects the constructivist foundations. Inforgetics
redefines the theoretical framework and accommodates models of complex systems,
in a way that do not reduce, or destroy the intelligibility of these. The neologism
of inforgetics may be considered parallel to energetics. Inforgetics focuses on
the relation between information and organisation, rather than on matter and
energy.
The
following will present the canonic model of information and its symbol, the
first and second principle of inforgetics. These are the manifestation of the
inforgetic theory.[29]
4.3.1. Information and its symbol
LMS
associates itself with Bateson’s (1972) definition of information: ‘a
difference which creates a difference’. In the shadow of PCE, this may be
re-written: ”/…/ a representation which transforms a representation /…/” (Le
Moigne 1990a:106). The operationalisation of this notion leads to the consideration
of two basic concepts, necessary for all modelling. These are: information and
its symbol; the latter is a physical support of the previous. The key issue concerns
the relations between these two concepts, or as Le Moigne (1990a:101) puts it:
”The development of complex systems modelling has long been comprised by the difficulty
of establishing a stable, non-reducing definition of joint concepts of
information and symbols.” Analytical modelling understands information in terms
of data, passive objects, pre-given to the modeller, well shadowed by the
positivist tradition. ”Each element of information had one and only one
attached significance, presumed established without ambiguity, one expressing
passive states, other disjoints expressing operations.” (Le Moigne 1990a:101).
Due
to the developments in semiology (C. Morris), communication theory (C. Shannon
& W. Weaver), theory of organisation (H. Quaster, H. von Foerster, H.
Atlan, E. Morin), anthropology (G. Bateson), cognition (J. Piaget, H. Simon),
the inforgetic paradigm disposes of a canonic model of information and its
symbol. This model accounts for the complexity of their relation and human
perceptions, which AM’s notion destroyed. (Le Moigne 1990a)
Information
is considered as a composition of forms (gestalt), or stable configuration of
symbols, which carry significance for its receiver with the intention to act
and which have been signified by deliberative formation. This may be expressed
by the conjunction of a sign (physical), capable of being at the same time, signified
(designation) and signifying (production of signified sense through symbols);
hence the inseparable conjunction: S3. The symbol is at the same
time physical support that is a recursive operator, assuring the function of designation
and production of symbols. The conceptualisation of a reflexive operator allows
the equivalence of value between operator and the operand (a symbol may be
signified as an operator and as an operand at the same time). This in turn
allows expression of complex phenomena perceived as recursive without reduction
and destruction - something that analytical modelling could not offer because
of its supporting logic of excluded thirds.
4.3.2. The first principle of Inforgetics: the
Principle of Self-organising
This
principle presents a generative mechanism of how an organisation organises
itself - hence a theory of self-organisation (Le Moigne 1990a, 1992). LMS
starts this exploration by emphasising the importance and by an examination of
C. Shannon’s (Shannon C.E. & Weaver W. 1949) ‘Mathematical theory of
communication’. Shannon emphasised that the theory focused exclusively on the
signal or symbol, ignoring the semantic and pragmatic quality of information.
W. Weaver in his introduction to that text, noted that information processing
should not be reduced entirely to technical signal processing. As Le Moigne
(1990a) notes, a contradiction occurred when an insignificant sign or symbol is
postulated while the significance of a sign’s probability was under consideration.
Identification of information separated from its context is not possible. It is
only identifiable in the context of its communication between the system of
emission and the system of reception; both are inseparable from the communication
system. (Le Moigne 1990a) When the epistemological spectacles are changed, the
pertinence of this model for mind and social sciences emerges, however. Because
it contributes to the intelligibility of a complex organisation, by being: ”/…/
a starting point for formulation and useful interpretation of all different
models of organising and autonomising information.” (Le Moigne 1990a:110) The
key aspect of Shannon’s model for the theory of self-organisation is that the
channel contains noise. This implies a transformation of the coded and
transmitted signal; hence the medium affects the message. This model manifests
the interdependency between the coding and the noise. (Le Moigne 1990a).
Next,
LMS takes account of H. Quaster’s (1964) model of transmission transformation.
Quaster’s consideration of Shannon’s model resulted in a formal model making
the transformation process of the transmitted signal intelligible. Briefly,
this model postulates that not all information emitted by the emitter is
received by the receiver, while the receiver receives some information that was
never emitted by the emitter. Consequently, the channel as such, transforms the
transmitted message due to the channel noise. Le Moigne (1990a) concludes:
”Even if the conditions of interpretation of Quaster’s model require great
caution in their interpretation, can one not say that it accounts for the most
common experience in communication between two systems, when one considers information
in its complexity: everyone knows that the other does not hear all that was
said to him and that he hears things that were not said to him. Because
everyone knows it, why then ignore it! Quaster’s model gives formal intelligibility
to this hypothesis /…/.” (Le Moigne 1990a:112)
The
important quality of Quaster’s model, which interpreted Shannon’s, makes LMS
ask the following question: ”How can one account for this process of loss and
gain of information in transmission, in the frequent case, when the emitting
and transmitting system are one and the same? /…/ or when the control system is
also the controlled system.” (Le Moigne 1990a:112). LMS notes that J. von
Neumann and R.W. Ashby started to tackle this issue in the fifties. In the case
of multiple finished state automation systems, von Neumann (1966) underlined however
that these applied to complicated systems only, not to complex systems. Ashby’s
(1956) principle of requisite variety on the other hand, considered as a
principle of self-organisation of systems, is only applicable when the number
of possible states of the self-organising system is known beforehand. Hence
according to Le Moigne (1990a) this is not useful for complex systems.
The
question above becomes intelligible due to the works of H. von Foerster (1959),
H. Atlan (1972 & 1979) and F. Varela (1979). On the apparent paradox of
self-organising systems, von Foerster proposed an original formalisation: the
system, while open to noise, as was discussed above, possesses the capacity of
adaptation possible by the single apparent feature of functioning. This notion
is expressed in the model: ‘Order from noise’, and takes into account the
findings of C. Shannon and H. Quaster. Following this line of inquiry, Atlan
re-discussed von Foerster’s notion, proposing a careful new formalisation and a
label that recognised this phenomenon more adequately; hence the model:
‘Complexity from noise’. On the other hand, Varela’s (1979) discussion of the
self-referential character of a self-informational process of a system,
proposed that the self-in-formation may be conceptualised as an endogenous
process of self-formation. This was in order to support the hypothesis of
internal action: organising information that is processed in and by the system.
Hence,
these models make the simultaneous process of information destruction and production
intelligible. This phenomenon may be perceived as a process of
self-transmitting, coding and de-coding of messages. In such an interpretation,
the complex process of emergence of new forms out of noise - not pre-programmed
- in the channel between the receiver and the emitter becomes intelligible.
Inforgetics accounts for the complex conception of information and organisation
that make complex system’s behaviour intelligible in a way that was not
possible previously - in the notion of energetics and analytical modelling. Or
as Le Moigne (1990a:113) puts it: ”/…/ joining the sign (a new form) and the significance,
led to recognition of a joint emergence of ‘new’ significance, in other word,
to make plausible the occurrence of ‘new’ possible behaviour of the considered
organisation. In processing information, it self-organises.”
The
organisation of information - that represents a complex phenomenon[30]
that a knower perceives or conceives - may be represented and exercised as such
by the Information Processing System.[31]
(This because IPS proposes a model that organises information.) This organisation
of information is expressed by the conjunction of the three functions: 1:
symbolic designation, which founds symbols in projective action, 2: symbolic
computation, which configures symbols and transforms them, 3: memorisation,
which registers symbolic configurations for accessibility. These three functions
permit the expression of the recursive character of the action of organisation,
which self-organises by in-formation. This implies an intelligible procedure
that considers information as an organisation - organising and organised,
therefore at the same time an operator and an operand. For the knower, to
organise is both an action of in-forming (computation) and the result of this
action (memorisation), it leads to designated organisation by information. The
second and the third function are easily visible in the complex conjunction
between the interaction of information and organisation, while the designation
of information is hidden under the surface. It will however become visible in
the decision processes, which mediate this interaction. These decision
processes are recognised in the second principle of inforgetics. (Le Moigne
1990a)
The
operational implications of this theorising, which resulted in the model of
complexification due to noise, suggest at least two necessary conditions for
the development of the endogenic process of self-organisation, and a better
potential for an autonomous system to adapt. These two conditions are: a) that
the system should be open to its environment, and b) that the system should
permit some internal redundancy, hence all recourses may not be permanently occupied.[32]
These qualities are of critical value for a system, because: ”When noise comes,
the system can attempt to reduce and decode it, then as the case may be, elaborate
new behaviours, by assimilation. It self-organises in producing forms of
original organisation, which it did not ‘import’ but which it self-produced (a
process of auto-poiesis).” (Le Moigne 1990a:116)
The
first principle of inforgetics, the principle of self-organisation or
equilibration, manifesting the processes where: information in-forms organised
organisation, which by organising, organises the formation of information,
hence in-formed, which…. (see Figure 4). This is in contrast to the first
principle of energetics that considers the mutual conservation between matter
and energy, which is also called the principle of entropy.
Figure
4.
Shows the principles of Inforgetic theory. Information informs (1) organised
organisation, which (2) organising organises the formation of in-formation (3)
thus informed, which (4)… This loop manifests relation between the two
principles of Inforgetic theory (i.e. the principle of self-organisation and
the principle of intelligent action) that is to say, the mental relation
between information and organisation mediated by decision. The figure also
shows the relation between the loop and the functions of the Information
Processing System.
4.3.3. The second principle of Inforgetics: the
Principle of Intelligent Action
In
order to explain the second principle of inforgetics, that is, the Principle of
Intelligent Action (PIA), a brief discussion of its paralleling principle will
first be presented. The latter is the second principle of energetics, that is
the Principle of Least Action (PLA), (also called the principle of natural
economy or maximum-from-minimum).
The
second principle (of both energetics and inforgetics) concerns decision-making,
in the present context. In the notion of energetics (and therefore analytical
modelling), when decisions are to be taken there is an aspiration for optimum
behaviour, presumed unique, for a given situation. Such an optimal decision is
considered to be guided by either a unique criterion or by so-called natural
laws. LMS’ critique of that notion notes that there is no real choice then,
because the decision is pre-determined. In the first case, predetermination is
due to a unique criterion of behaviour, which mostly refers to the PLA. It is
given by physicists as a natural law and imposes the axiom of doing maximum-from-minimum.
The second case may be manifested by the constraints through which the environment
is perceived. The system can only subject itself to eternal laws that constrain
it and guide its behaviour. Therefore, to know these laws implies being able to
predetermine ulterior behaviours in the system, and hence decision making of
the system. (Le Moigne 1989b, 1990a, 1990b, 1995c, 1995d). AM’s concept of decision
making is exercised with algorithms that determine behaviours of a system.
These algorithms rest on disjunctive logic axiomatics. These are also often
accompanied with some factors, such as uncertainty and risk. The algorithms are
often presented as those of mathematical decision theory or normative decision
theory. Hence, AM’s conception of decision implies an optimum command received
by the system for establishing good rational behaviour. LMS’ critique notes
that this conception leads to a situation, that mathematicians call undecidable,
where it is not possible to calculate in a certain and singular way an optimum
solution to the stated problem. The paradox occurs when theories on the one
hand postulate an undecidable situation, while on the other human actors are
able to pragmatically decide by using deliberate reason and without the
algorithms. Hence, SM accuses AM of reducing perceived complexity by ignoring
the capacity of human actors, such as intelligence, conception, imagination,
intention and memory. Therefore, LMS considers AM’s use of energetics for
decision making to be suitable sometimes for complicated, closed and
predictable systems, such as programmed automata only. It is not the case for
complex, open and unpredictable systems. (Le Moigne 1990a)
LMS’
theory of inforgetics offers an alternative to PLA due to its Principle of
Intelligent Action (PIA). Le Moigne illustrates PIA with the following Marxian
metaphor:
”The
bee surprises the ability of more than one architect by the perfection of its
wax cells, but what makes the most mediocre architect superior to the most
expert bee, is that he constructs the cell in his head before constructing it
in the hive.” (K. Marx, Capital, vol.1, p.174)
PIA
is derived from A. Newell and H.A. Simon’s work (1976) who investigate the capacity
of the cognitive system to explore and construct symbolic representations of
processed knowledge. PIA may be defined as the cognitive process through which
the mind constructs a representation of dissonance (gap), which it perceives
between its behaviours (is-situation/s) and its projects (ought-to-be situation/s),
and seeking to invent some responses or plans of action, capable of restoring a
wanted concordance (no-gap) - an intelligent (adaptive) action (Le Moigne
1995b). PIA focuses on dialectical models, which favour examination of previous
experiences, by using heuristic reasoning for problem solving, hence founded on
inductive reasoning rather than deductive, then searching feasibility or
adequacy rather than objective and optimal truth. The architect in the parable
is constrained like the bee by the epistemological foundation of positivist epistemologies.
Changing the epistemological spectacles, the architect may offer himself other
criteria than the sole minimisation of wax, such as ethics, aesthetics, weight,
etc. Further and at least as important, the list he chooses is not
predetermined by energetic laws, but rather created by his intellectual
ability. (Le Moigne 1995b)
4.3.3.1. The canonic model of the decision process.
LMS
also offers an implementation of the second principle of inforgetics, by
establishing a canonic model of the decision process in complex systems. This
is derived from Simon’s works on problem solving.
LMS’
model is founded on Simon’s two hypotheses about decision making which are: a)
decision is intelligence, that is teleological comprehension, and may be
represented by the process of identification-formulation of problems: what are
the objectives and what is the present situation; b) decision is design (conception);
a cognitive process of problem solution. The conjunction of these two
hypotheses allows modelling of decision processes in a general way. SM proposes
two complementary implementations of decision process modelling. First,
decision may be considered a stable system of symbolic manipulation, and hence
represented by an exercise of symbolic computation (an IPS). Secondly, the
decision process may be represented by a conjunction of three stable
subsystems, which are in themselves recursive. These three subsystems are: a) a
system of intelligence: problem formulation, b) a system of design: problem
solution, and c) a system of selection: multi-criteria choice of decision action.
This model stresses some important qualities. First, a decision process in
complex systems is fundamentally teleological. Secondly, the problems are not
previously given but constructed by the modeller, hence there is
self-finalisation. (Le Moigne 1990a)
The
essential difference between AM and SM is that AM considers the decision-making
act as a result, capable of being analysed and disjoined. While SM considers
decision-making as a sequential process of information processing, developed
inside a complex organisation, from which it is not separable. SM considers the
problem of decision-making in complex situations to be one of qualitative
representation, rather than of quantification and algorithms. The main issue
then is how to represent, and consequently of what-to-do; rather than of
how-to-do or solve by algorithms, as AM stresses (Le Moigne 1990a). Further, in
complex situations all decisions are multi-criteria decisions; that is, there
exists more than one satisfactory solution to a single multi-criteria
selection, but no single optimum solution. The optimum may be found in simple,
(closed and well-structured) mono-criteria situations. Therefore heuristic
reasoning, searching for satisfying solutions is preferred, rather than
algorithmic reasoning looking for an optimal solution, which may never be found
in complex, multi-criteria situations. (Le Moigne 1990a; Le Moigne &
Bourgine 1990d) For an overview of the two discussed paradigms see Table 9.
PARADIGM OF NATURAL UNIVERSE: |
1st Natural Universe: ENERGETICS |
2nd Natural Universe: INFORGETICS |
|
Concerns: |
The process of conversion between energy and
matter, and vice versa; concerns natural sciences |
The conceptual interaction between
information and organisation, and vice versa, mediated by decision of
intelligence; concerns mind and social sciences |
|
Notion of Information: |
Passive and disjuncted data, without
ambiguity |
S3: deliberately Signified Sign making
Signification; complex conjunction of the operator and the operand |
|
1st Principle: |
Principle of mutual conservation between
Energy and Matter (PEM); |
Principle of Self-Organisation (PSO); or
principle of equilibration |
|
2nd Principle: |
Principle of Least Action (PLA); or principle
of maximum-from-minimum |
Principle of general Intelligent Action
(PIA); or principle of teleological adaptive behaviour |
|
some |
searches for: |
a unique optimum |
a satisfaction or adequacy |
characteristics of the 2nd |
focuses: |
quantity, hence: How-to-do? |
quality/representation, hence: What-to-do? |
principle: |
uses: |
algorithms |
heuristics |
|
qualities of the domain of concern: |
determinative, closed, mono-criterion,
pre-determined systems; |
deliberative, open, multi-criteria,
unpredictable systems; |
Table
9. Shows
a juxtaposition of the two natural universes of human experiences, that is to
say the energetic and the inforgetic. These are founded on the two
epistemological positions, the positivist and realist paradigms and the
constructivist paradigm, respectively.
5. A summing up the significance of LMS
Le
Moigne’s contribution will certainly need to be critically evaluated from
different perspectives in order to assess its particular value. One attempt has
been done by Eriksson (1997). In this section, the author will attempt to
briefly sum up what he thinks is Le Moigne’s significant contribution.
Le
Moigne’s contribution can be considered impressive in its ability to scan a
very large amount of research findings from diverse domains, identify and
extract the crucial ideas, and transform and relate these to each other, in a
way that few would expect possible. Le Moigne is primarily occupied with the
meta-modelling of theories. In this manner his contributions may be considered
as follows.
5.1. Epistemological formulation
Le
Moigne’s formalisation of the basic assumptions of constructivist
epistemologies (Le Moigne 1995b) into a coherent framework is important,
especially if this domain is to be considered teachable. The crucial argument
of theory validation is easily visible and it offers a reasonable alternative
to the objectivist and relativist positions. This formalisation framework helps
us to understand the similarities and differences between the different
theories of human mental constructions, such as constructivism as a doctrine,
constructivist epistemology, social construction theory, social construction of
technology, etc., with several branches within each mentioned. Constructivist
epistemologies establish a firm foundation for designed, artificial,
engineered, organised systems - or in LMS’ notion for systems science. These
domains may manifest their epistemological foundations without being reduced to
the so-called applied sciences. These foundations are justified just as well as
those of the analytical sciences.
5.2. General Systems Theory
Le
Moigne presents (1977-1994) a formalisation of a General Systems Theory (GST)
and a distinction of the different modelling paradigms. He syntheses the
cybernetic model with the structuralist one, resulting in the systemic model.
GST has been around as a concept at least since L. von Bertalanffy. It seems
though that there has been a lot of confusion about what it really implies. In
von Bertalanffy’s notion - without neglecting his contribution - it seems to be
primarily a theory of open systems. Further, GST has been often confused with
cybernetics and considered to be one and the same (for example Ericson 1972).
Le Moigne makes it clear that cybernetics and GST, although overlapping, are
two different theories.
Le
Moigne’s notion of an a priori systemic model of system levels (DIOS) comprised
of the decision system, memorisation-information system and operation system
informs the cybernetic notion, comprised of two systems: the decision-making
and the operating systems. In cybernetic terms the operation system must obey
the directives of its decision system and eventually report to the latter. The
cybernetic model manifests some misconceptions when considered in relation to
the systemic one. When applied to psychological and social domains, the
implications of constructivist epistemologies state that this one-to-one relation
(realist/positivist) may not be assumed, because mental schemes fit the experiences
of the cogniser rather then match the ontic reality. Furthermore the cognitive
system manifests intelligence, memory, imagination, etc. and the relation
between the decision-making system and the operating system is of a complex
nature, represented in the systemic model by a memorisation system.
5.3. Theory of an active organisation
Similar
to GST, LMS offers a formalisation of the theory of active organisation. He has
enriched Morin’s notion with recursiveness and presented something that is
distinct from the traditional invariant or passive notion of organisation. The
active notion recognises, for example, that organisation is perception of an observer
(hence necessary active), and that it manifests pluralism and power relations.
5.4. Inforgetic Theory
Inforgetics
offers the modeller a foundation for the psychological and social sciences in
terms other than those of the traditional positivistic approach. Hence, the
notion that mind and social domains are fuzzy or less exact than the domains of
the natural science, is a misconception in the light of Inforgetic theory. This
is because the statement of fuzziness or of what is exact or not, is postulated
in reference to the energetic foundations, the latter being presupposed. As
pointed out by Bateson and Le Moigne, a change of the scientific domain should
be accompanied by a mediation of the epistemological foundation of their
inquiry.
The
inforgetic principle of self-organisation manifests a plausible theory of how
open systems self-organise. It is founded on established and rather stable
research findings of Shannon and Weaver, von Foerster, Quaster, Atlan and
Varela. The same may be said of the principle of intelligent action, established
by Simon’s life long research in decision and cognitive science. Le Moigne’s
conjunction of the two aspects of inforgetics into one single framework may be
considered original (information in-forms organisation which in turn organises
information, which…; this loop is according to Le Moigne mediated by the
decision of an intelligence, with capacities of imagination, memory, etc.).
Such a notion recognises human beings as intelligent - both emotional and
rational. This is in contrast to attempts by chaos or fuzzy set theory that
reduce intelligence to mere chance.
5.5. The grand synthesis
Le
Moigne has succeeded in synthesising the very different and rich research
findings into one single and coherent system of thought. The foundations of
projective constructivist epistemology are clearly visible in the procedural rationality
mode, the general systems theory, the Eco-Auto-Re-organisation paradigm, and
the inforgetic theory, these four clearly interacting with each other. The
whole framework manifests a conjunction of research exercised both in Europe
and in America, at different times and in different intellectual traditions.
Acknowledgement
I
would like to express my gratitude to Professor Jean-Louis Le Moigne for his
help and guidance in my studies of systemics. This also applies to his student
Mr. Pascal Vidal. Mrs. E. Mostovac’s help with the French prose was pivotal in
this work. Mrs. V. de Raadt and Dr. A. Basden’s help with the English prose was
essential for the present article. I would also like to thank the anonymous
reviewers and the editor of this journal for valuable suggestions for modifications.
Any misconception in this text however, ought to be assigned exclusively to the
present author. Further, the support given by the Department of Informatics at
Mid Sweden University and the Department of Informatics and Systems Science at
Luleå University of Technology has been significant.
References
Adreit F. (1994). Une modélisation <<Orientée Project>>
Contribution à l’Ingénierie des Systèmes d’Information. Note de Recherche no. 94-14, GRASCE, Universite d’Aix Marseille
III, Aix-en-Provence Cedex 1, France.
Ashby, W.R., (1956). An
introduction to cybernetics. Chapman & Hall. Ltd., Londres
Atlan H. (1972). L’organisation biologique
et la théorie de l’information. Ed. Herman, Paris.
Atlan H. (1979). Entre le cristal
et la fumée. Essai sur l’organisation du vivant. Ed. du Seuil, Paris.
Avenier M.J. (1992a). The new strategic eco-management framework for the
new strategic information system technologies: From a control-based to a
knowledge-based organisation. Note de
Recherche no. 92-13, June, GRASCE, Universite d’Aix Marseille III,
Aix-en-Provence Cedex 1, France.
Avenier M.J. (1992b). Strategic eco-management: an alternative framework
for modelling business processes. Note de Recherche no. 92-14, June,
GRASCE, Universite d’Aix Marseille III, Aix-en-Provence Cedex 1, France.
Avenier M.J. (1995). L’ingéniérie de l’action stratégique en milieu
complexe: repe?res. Proceedings of 5th AIMS Conference, Paris, May.
Avenier M.J. (1996). A “Boundaryless Company”: from concepts to
practice. Presented at the 3rd
Congres Mondial IFSAM, 8-11 July, Paris.
Bateson
G. (1972). Steps to an ecology of mind.
Ballentine Book., New York.
Bartoli J.A. (1991a). Vers une méthodologie de conception de systèmes
d’information intelligents. In: Le
pilotage stratégique de l’enterprise revisité. Du pilotage cybernétique à la
stratégie systémique. Cahier no.1, September 1992. GRASCE, Université d’Aix
Marseille III, Centre Forbin-Austrelitz 15-19 Allée Claude Forbin - 13627
Aix-en-Provence Cedex 1, France.
Bartoli, J.A. (1991b). Cooperative network of intelligent units for
logistic control. Note de Recherche
no. 91-05, Mars, GRASCE, Universite d’Aix Marseille III, Aix-en Provence Cedex
1, France.
Bartoli J.A. (1992). Business Models: a framework for corporate
knowledge repository. Proceedings of
International Conference on Economics and Artificial Intelligence (CEMIT
92-CECOIA III), Tokyo, pp. 261-264.
Bartoli, J.A. (1994a). Système d’information intelligent pour le
controle de flux logitique. In: Intelligence
de l’organisation et systemes d’information strategiques. Cahier no. 4-5,
December 1994. GRASCE, Université d’Aix Marseille III, Centre Forbin-Austrelitz
15-19 Allée Claude Forbin - 13627 Aix-en-Provence Cedex 1, France.
Bartoli J.A. (1994b). SYLI: Sytème logistique intelligent. In: Intelligence de l’organisation et systemes
d’information strategiques. Cahier no. 4-5, December 1994. GRASCE, Université
d’Aix Marseille III, Centre Forbin-Austrelitz 15-19 Allée Claude Forbin - 13627
Aix-en-Provence Cedex 1, France.
Beer S. (1979). The heart of
enterprise. Wiley, London.
Beer S. (1981). Brain and the firm.
2nd ed., Wiley, London.
Betz F., Mitroff I. (1974). Representational systems theory. Management Science, vol. 20, no. 9, pp.
1242-1252.
Bogdanov A. (1980). Essays in
tektology. 1913-1920, (English translation by G. Gorelik),
Intersystems Publication, Seaside, C.A.
Boudon R. (1968). A quoi sert la notion
de structure? Gallimard, Paris.
Bouldning K.E. (1956). General systems theory, the skeleton of science. Management Science, vol.2, April.
Ericson R.F. (1972). Visions of cybernetic organisations. Academy of Management Journal, vol. 15,
pp, 427-443.
Eriksson D.M. (1996). Organisational information system: Extending
organisational cognition through intelligent artefacts. Cybernetics and Systems, vol. 27, no. 3. pp.235-263.
Eriksson D.M. (1997). Post-modernity and systems science: An evaluation
of J-L Le Moigne’s contribution to the management of the present civilisation. Systems Practice, in press.
Dobzhansky,
T. (1962). Mankind evolving. New
Haven, Yale Univ.Press.
Dubos R. (1981). We shall Have to get Away from Claude Bernard. Co-evolution, no. 6, Autumn, pp. 28-32.
Dupuy J.P. (1986). Autonomy and complexity in sociology. In: The science and praxis of complexity.
United Nations University, Tokyo, pp. 255-266.
Foerster von H. (1959). On the self-organizing systems and on their
environment. In: H. von Foerster 1984.
Foerster von H. (1984). Observing
systems. Intersystems Publications Seaside, C.A. 2nd ed.
Gigch van J. P. (1996). Book Reviews. Systems Research, vol.13, no.4, pp.495-498.
Glaserfeld
von E. (1995). Radical Constructivism. A
way of knowing and learning. The Falmer Press, London.
Korzybsky A, (1933-1980). Science
and Sanity. An introduction to non-Aristotelian systems and general semantics.
4th Lakeville (Conn.). The International Non-Aristotelician Lib.
Pub. Cy.
Ladriere
(1975). La structure des révolutions
scientifiques. Flammarion, Paris.
Le Moigne J.L. (1973). Les
systemes d’information dans les organisations. PUF, Paris.
Le Moigne J.L. (1974a). Les
systemes de décision dans les organisations. PUF, Paris.
Le Moigne J.L. (1974b). The ‘manager-terminal-model’ system is also a
system. In: Information Processing 74,
pp. 946-951, North-Holland Pub.Comp.
Le Moigne J.L. (1975). The four-flows model as a tool for designing the
information system of an organization. In: Information
Systems and Organizational Structure. Grochla E., Szyperski N. (ed.), pp.
324-341, Walter de Gruyter, Berlin
Le Moigne J.L. (1976a). Repères bibliographiques sur la théorie des
systèmes ouvertes et la cybernétique. Note
de Recherche no. 76-11, GRASCE, Universite d’Aix Marseille III,
Aix-en-Provence Cedex 1, France.
Le Moigne J.L. (1976b). Répresentation succincte et historique de la
théorie des systèmes ouvertes et de la cybernétique. Note de Recherche no. 76-12, GRASCE, Universite d’Aix Marseille
III, Aix-en-Provence Cedex 1, France.
Le Moigne J.L., Landry M., (1977a). Towards a theory of organizational
information system - A general system perspective. In: Information Processing 77, IFIP, North-Holland Publishing Company,
Gilchrist B. ed., pp. 801-805.
Le Moigne J.L., Carré D. (1977b). Auto-organisation
del’enterprise. 50 propositions pour l’autogestion.
Les Editions d’organisations, Paris.
Le Moigne J.L. (1977c). Elements bibliographiques d’analyse de systeme. Note de Recherche no. 77-14, GRASCE,
Universite d’Aix Marseille III, Aix-en-Provence Cedex 1, France.
Le Moigne (1977-1994). La théorie
du systeme géneral. Théorie de la modélisation. PUF, Paris.
Le Moigne J.L., Pascot D. (ed.), (1979b). Les processus collectifs de mémorisation. Mémoire et Organisation.
Librare de l’Universite, Aix-en-Provence.
Le Moigne J.L. (1980a). Une axiomatique: les regles du jeu de la
modélisation systémique. Economies et
Societes, vol. 14, no. 6, pp. 1159-1178.
Le Moigen J.L. (1980b). L’analyse du Systeme, Malgre tout… La Pensée, févril, pp. 63-78.
Le Moigne J.L. (1981). Transmettre, calculer, communiquer?:
co-mémoriser; quelques perspectives pour le développement de la télématique
dans la société. In: CITEL: La conception
des systémes télématiques. AFCET/CITEL, Nice, pp.3-13.
Le Moigne J.L. (1982). Les sciences de la decision: Sciences d’analyse
ou sciences du genie? Interpretations epistemologiques. Note de Recherche, no. 82-08, 1982, GRASCE, Universite d’Aix
Marseille III, Aix-en-Provence Cedex 1, France.
Le Moigne (1983a). Science de l’autonomie et autonomie de la science.
In: L’auto-organisation, de la physique
au politique. Dumonchel P., Dupuy J.P. (eds.), pp.521-536.
Le Moigne J.L. (1983b). Le vieillissement des organisations sociales. Communications, 37, pp. 181-194, Ed. du
Seuil.
Le Moigne J.L. (1984a). Trois theoremes da la theorie generale de
l’organisation. Note de Recherche,
no. 84-17, 1984, GRASCE, Universite d’Aix Marseille III, Aix-en-Provence Cedex
1, France.
Le Moigne J.L. (1984b). Le paradoxes de l’ingénieur. Culture Technique, 12, Mars, pp.
327-335.
Le Moigne J.L. & Vérin H. (1984c). Sur le processus d’autonomisation
des sciences du génie. Cahiers STS
(CNRS) 2, pp. 42-55.
Le Moigne J.L. (1984d). Qu’est-ce qu’un modele? Confrontation Psychriatique, 3, pp.11-36.
Le Moigne J.L., Atias C. (1984). Science
et conscience de la complexite. Librairie de l’universite, Aix-en-Provence.
Le Moigne J.L. (1985a). The intelligence of complexity. In: The science and praxis of complexity.
The United Nations University, pp. 35-61.
Le Moigne J.L. (1985b). Towards new epistemological foundations for
information systems. Systems Research,
vol. 2, no. 3, pp. 247-251.
Le Moigne J.L. (1986a). Les sciences de la décision: sciences d’analyse
ou sciences de génie? Interprétations épistémologiques. In: L’Aide à la décision. Nadeau R., Landry
M. (ed.), Les Presses de l’Université Laval Qubéc, Canada. pp. 3-52.
Le Moigne J.L. (1986b). Vers un système d’information organisationnel? Revue Française de Gestion,
novembre-decembre pp. 20-31.
Le Moigne J.L., Sibley E.H. (1986). Information-Organization-Decision:
Some strange loops. Information &
Management, vol. 11, pp. 237-244.
Le Moigne J.L. (1987a). Systemographie de l’enterprise. Revue Internationale de Systemique, vol.
2, no. 4.
La Moigne J.L. (1987b). Les nouvellers sciences son bien des sciences.
Reperes historique et éistémologiques. Revue
Internationale de Systemique, vol.1, no.3, pp.295-318.
Le Moigne J.L. (1989a). Systems profile: first joining. Systems Research, vol. 6, No. 4,
Le Moigne J.L. (1989b). Natural and artificial computing and reasoning
in economic affairs. Theory and Decision,
27, pp. 107-116.
Le Moigne J.L. (1989c). Quelle épistémologie pour une science des
systémes naturels <<Qui sont avec cela artificiels>>? Revue Internationale de Systemique, vol.
3, no. 3, pp. 251-271.
Le Moigne J.L., van Gigch J.P. (1989). A paradigmatic approach to the
discipline of information systems. Behavioural
Science, vol. 34, pp. 128-147.
Le
Moigne J.L. (1990a). La modélisation des
systèmes complexes. Dunod, Paris.
Le Moigne J.L. (1990b). Intelligence Artificielle et Raisonnement
Economique. Mondes en Developement,
vol. 18, no. 72, pp. 11-18.
Le Moigne J.L. (1990c). Systémique et complexité. Études d’épistemologie
systémique. Revue Internationale de
Systémique, vol. 4, no. 2, pp. 107-117.
Le Moigne J.L., Bourgine P. (1990d). Les ”Bonnes Decisions” Sont-Elles
Optimales ou Adequates? Operational
Research ’90. Selected Pappers from the Twelfth IFORS International Conference on Operational
Research. Bradley H. (ed.), 1st ed. 1991, B.P.C.C. Wheatons Ltd.
Exeter, U.K.
Le Moigne J.L., van Gigch J.P. (1990e). The design of an organization
information system. Intelligent artifacts for complex organizations. Information & Management, 19, pp.
325-331.
Le Moigne J.L. (1991a). Le conception des systemes d’information
organisationnels: de l’ingenierie informatique a l’ingenierie des systemes.
Presented at: Congres “Autour et a l’entour de MERISE”, AFCET,
Sophia-Antipolis, 17-19 Avril 1991. Also in: Intelligence de l’organisation ert
systemes d’information strategiques, Les
Cahiers du GRASCE, no. 4-5,
1994, pp. 13-31, Universite d’Aix Marseille III, Aix-en- Provence Cedex 1, France. And in: Le Moigne J.L., J.A.
Bartoli 1997 (eds.).
Le Moigne J.L. (1991b). Épistémologie de la science des systèmes. In: Handbook of systems science, Cleris de
M., European Systems Union-Hellenic Systems Society, Athens.
Le Moigne J.L. (1992). The ”Second Princpile” of organizational
engeeniring: The general intelligent action principle. In: Organisation, economie, Intelligence, pp. 3-8, GRASCE, Université
d’Aix-Marseille III, Aix-en-provence, Cedex 1, France.
Le Moigne J.L., Alcaras J.R., Dehaene P. (1992). Socio-economics as a
new engineering science: Designing sustainable complex social organizations as
”Evolving artifacts”. Note de Recherche
no. 92-09, May, GRASCE, Universite d’Aix Marseille III, Aix-en-Provence Cedex
1, France.
Le Moigne J.L. (1993). Formalism of systemic modelling. In: Some Physicochemical and Mathematical Tools
for Understanding of Living Systems., Greppin H., Bonzon M., Degli Agosti
R., eds. University of Geneva.
Le Moigne J.L. (1994). Le
Constructivisme tome 1: Des fondements. ESF éditeur, Paris.
Le Moigne J.L., Bartoli J.A. (1994). Qualitative reasoning and complex
symbol processing. Mathematics and
Computers in Simulation, 36, pp. 129-136.
Le Moigne J.L. (1995a). Le
Constructivisme tome 2: Des épistémologies. ESF éditeur, Paris
Le
Moigne J.L. (1995b). Que sais - je? Les
épistémologies constructivistes. PUF, Paris.
Le Moigne J.L. (1995c). On theorizing the complexity of economic systems. The journal of socio-economics, vol.
24, pp. 477-499.
Le Moigne J.L. (1995d). If you do believe that your industrial system
really is complex, then… Recherche
opérationnelle/Operations Research, vol. 29, no. 3, pp. 225-243.
Le Moigne J.L., Bartoli J.A., eds. (1997). Organisation de
l’intelligence et intelligence de l’organisation. Economica, Paris.
Marx, Karl (1930). Capital.
Transl. from the fourth German ed. by Eden and Cedar Paul. Introd. by G.D.H.
Cole London 1930, Vol. 1-2
McCulloch
W. & Pitt W. (1943). A logical calculus of the ideas immanent in nervous activity.
Bulletin of Mathematical Biophysics,
vol. 5, pp. 115-133
Morin E. (1977). La Méthode 1. La
Nature de la Nature. Editions du Seuil, Paris.
Morin E. (1980). La Méthode 2. La
Vie de la Vie. Editions du Seuil, Paris.
Morin E. (1982). Science avec
Conscience. Fayard, Paris.
Morin E. (1982). Can we conceive of a science of autonomy? Human Systems Management, 3, pp.
201-206.
Morin E. (1986). La Méthode 3. La
Connaissance de la Connaissance. Editions du Seuil, Paris.
Morin E. (1991). Les idées.
Editions du Seuil, Paris.
Morin E. (1992). Method. Toward a
study of humankind. Volume 1: The Nature of Nature. Translated and
introduced by: J.L.R. Bélanger. Peter Lang, New York.
Neumann von, J. (1966). The theory
of self-reproducing automata. University of Illinois Press, Urbana, IL.
Newell A., Simon H.A. (1972). Human
problem solving. Prentice-Hall, Inc. Englewood Cliffs. N.J.
Orillard M. (1992). Décisions collectives: représentation et
coordination des initiatives dans un
environment complexe. In: Le pilotage stratégique de l’enterprise revisité. Du
pilotage cybernétique à la stratégie systémique. Cahier no.1, September 1992.
GRASCE, Université d’Aix Marseille III, Centre Forbin-Austrelitz 15-19 Allée
Claude Forbin - 13627 Aix-en-Provence Cedex 1, France.
Pascal B. (1963). Oeuvres
complètes. Seuil, Paris.
Piaget J. (1937). La construction
du rél chez l’enfant, Neuchatel, Delachaux et Niestlé. (The construction of
reality in the child. Translation M. Cook, New York, Basic Books, 1971).
Piaget J., ed. (1967). Logique et
connaissance scientifique. Gallimard-Encyclopédie de la Pléiade, Paris.
Piaget J. (1968). La
structuralisme. PUF, Paris.
Piaget J. (1970). L’épistémologie
génétique. PUF, Paris,
Piaget
J. & Garcia B. (1987). Vers une
logique des significations, ed. Murionde Geneva.
Popper K.R. (1959). The logic of
scientific discovery. Harper & Row, New York.
Prigogine
I., Stengers I. (1979). La nouvelle
alliance. Paris, Gallimard, NRF.
Quang P.T., Charter-Kastler C. (1991). Merise in practice. London, Macmillan Education.
Quastler H. (1964). The emergence of biological organization. Yale
University Press, New Haven.
Shannon C.E., Weaver W. (1949). A
mathematical theory of communication. 11th ed., 1967, University of Illinois Press, Urbana
Illinois.
Simon H.A. (1960). The new science
of management decision. New York, Harper & Row Pub.
Simon H.A. (1969). The sciences of
the artificial. MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass.
Simon
H.A. (1973). Does scientific discovery have a logic? In: Simon (1977)
Simon H.A. (1976a). Administrative
Behavior. 3rd ed. Free Press, New York.
Simon H.A. (1976b). From substantive to procedural rationality. In:
Simon 1982.
Simon H.A. (1977). Models of
discovery. D. Reidel Pub., Dordrecht, Holland.
Simon H.A. (1982). Models of
Bounded Rationality. MIT Press, Cambridge Mass.
Simon
H.A. (1983). Reasoning in Human Affairs.
Standford University Press, Ca.
Varela F. J. (1975). A calculus for self-reference. Int. J. Gen. Syst. Vol.2, pp.5-24.
Varela F. J. (1977). Circulus fructuosus: Revisiting self-reference as a
scientific notion. In: Proceedings of
Annual Meeting of Society for General Systems Research”, Denever, Colorado,
pp. 116-118.
Varela F.J. (1979). Principles of
biological autonomy. North Holland Pub., New York.
Vico G.B. (1710). De la Tres
Ancienne Philosophie des Peuples Italiques., (translated from Latin by Mailhos G. And Granel G.,
Trans European Express, 1987).
Vidal P. (1996). Cognitive ecology and new information and communication
technology. Towards new perspectives in organisational intelligence design.
Presented at the 1996 International Conference
of the Swedish Operations Research Association on: Managing the Technological
Society: The next century’s challenge to O.R. 1 - 3 October 1996. Department
of Informatics and Systems Science, Lulea University of Technology, SE-971 87
Lulea, Sweden.
Watzlawick P. (1977). How real is
real? New York, Vintage.
Watzlawick P. (1984). The invented
reality. New York, Norton.
Weaver
W. (1948). Science and complexity. American
Scientist, 36, p.536-544.
Wiener N., Rosenblueth A., Bigelow J. (1943). Behaviour, Purpose and
Teleology. Philosophy of Science,
vol. 10, pp. 18-24.
Wiener N. (1948). Cybernetics or
control and communication in the animal and machine. The MIT Press, Mass.
Zannetos Z.S. (1968). Toward intelligent management information systems.
Industrial Management Review,
Cambridge-Mass., MIT, vol. 9, no. 3, spring.
Notes
[1] The present author’s intellectual contribution is only a summary of J-L
Le Moigne’s original publications over the last 25 years.
[3] ”The Theory of General System is a collective work, one of a
generation. It is not a property of a school, nor of a nation, nor of a discipline.”
(Le Moigne 1977-1994:2).
[4] The original texts of LMS often make the presentation of its ideas in
contrast to the positivist and the realist paradigms (Le Moigne 1991b). Such an
approach will be used here in order to facilitate intelligibility.
[5] The three questions elegantly manifest the canonic model of the general
system (GS) of LMS, where the what expresses the structural quality, the how
manifests the functional quality, while the why the transformational. GS will
be discussed further on in this presentation. These three questions are also
given by Piaget (1967).
[6] For a brief review of Le Moigne’s main texts on constructivist
epistemology see van Gigch (1996).
[7] PCE is fundamentally influenced by J. Piaget’s works on cognition (for
example: Piaget 1937, 1970). His mission was to explain knowledge in biological
rather than philosophical terms. This resulted in a theory of cognition that
considers the function of human knowing as adaptive in the biological sense,
the goal of this adaptation is to provide viability to the cognising organism.
Le Moigne does not present Piaget’s theory in his own works, he rather assumes
that the reader is already familiar with these and consequently builds his own
reasoning on that assumption. It is beyond the scope of this text to change
that assumption. Hence, the reader ought to be somewhat familiar with the key
issues in Piaget’s works, he may also consult von Glaserfeld’s (1995) recent
presentation.
[10] Transductive reasoning refers to the possibility of transducing or
transferring reasoning from one domain to another, due to a certain degree of
homomorphism. Retroduction refers to the reasoning ability due to feedback.
[11] In other words, the teleological precept means that the observer should
ask what is/are the goal/s of the observed phenomenon and then what is the behaviour
and the environment that relates to the goal/s, without worrying too much about
what that phenomenon may be made of, its internal structure. When plausible
theses of this kind are acquired, then the procedure of understanding may
proceed with hypothesising the internal structure of the experienced phenomenon.
[12] Le Moigne (1990 & 1977-1994) presents a plausible model of complex
behaviour emergence, which may be intelligible, yet not necessary explicable.
[13] Mono-criterion problems have one criterion that determines the choice
of means for problem solving. Multi-criteria problems have many, most often
contradicting criteria that do not allow to find one optimal solution but
rather several satisfying solutions.
[17] Le Moigne (1977-94:77) defines isomorphism as: “A bi-jective
correspondence, such that to each element of the beginning ensemble (the model)
only one element of the end ensemble (object) and reciprocally corresponds.
This correspondence is transitive, reflexive and symmetrical.” In other words
isomorphism refers to the same forms.
[18] Le Moigne (1977-94:77) defines homomorphism as: “A sur-jective
correspondence, such that to each element of a beginning ensemble corresponds
at least one element of the end ensemble, without reciprocity. This correspondence
is transitive and reflexive but not symmetrical.” In other words, homomorphism
refers to similar forms.
[20] J.P. Dupuy’s definition is: ”By genotype, I mean a matrix, a structure,
a mechanism, a rule by which to play. Thus it is not necessarily the genome of
a living being... What are the phenotypes that this genotype is capable of producing
or likely to engender? Today we know that even for very simple and particularly
deterministic genotypes, the answer to this question may be inextricable
complex: because phenotypes themselves are complex, because the whole they make
up constitutes an inexhaustible wealth, because during the transition from
genotype to phenotype problems of calculability arise which are difficult, if
not impossible to resolve... Even when it is a mere figment of the imagination,
a genotype or model is nonetheless endowed with a certain autonomy and able to
produce the novel and the unexpected... The transition from genotype to phenotype
would imply not the actualisation of a potential but the achievement of
virtuality.” (J.P. Dupuy 1986:255-256).
[21] The concept of form is due to the Gestalt theory, elaborated in the
beginning of this century, in order to take account the psychology of perception.
LMS then, defines gestalt as: ”/.../ a perceived field, by that which is
distinctive from depth, in a sufficient stable manner, from which however, it
is inseparable. It emerges by structuring (formation of patterns) although its
shape seems to belong to it, whether this structuring is geometric or
conceptual.” (Le Moigne 1990a:47).
[22] The reader may observe the correspondence between the two genotypes of
GP and IPS. Both focus on the three aspects: time = memory, space =
communication, form = computation.
[26] Boulding’s (1956) nine levels manifest increasing complexity of
phenomena in science as follows: frameworks, clockworks, thermostats or
cybernetic systems, open systems, genetic-societal systems, animal systems,
human systems, social organisations and transcendental systems.
[28] The reader may note the relation of these three recursive functions to
the canonical models of General Process and of Information Processing System.
That is: link = space, communication; produce = form, computation; maintain =
time, memorisation.
[29] LMS’ Inforgetic
paradigm offers also an Inforgetic model of an organisation, which is a
conjunction of the DIOS model and the EARO paradigm. This model is not
presented in the present text however, because of the limited published
information that describes it.
[30] Because organisation of information by an IPS represents a complex
perception or conception then it also represents a General System and a DIOS.
[31] This discussion focuses on the organisation of information and their
symbols processed by an IPS. While
the previously given account of IPS in this text, focussed IPS as processing information. Hence, the IPS’ two
modes have together four basic functions: to generate, to memorise, to
communicate and to compute information. The last three are intertwined and
recursively related to the first (Le Moigne 1990a).